Site hosted by Angelfire.com: Build your free website today!

el despertador

despiertos
no lo despierta ... pero le daña la mañana
el bejuco del alba
intro

 

 fuente

 

 

editorial
opinión
 

The International Journal of Transdisciplinary Studies Vol. 1,(1): 00-00. 1997

Rethinking Institutions in Societies of Control

Miquel Domènech and Francisco J. Tirado


Weber (allowing time out for his lengthy 'nervous breakdown') closes thenineteenth century for us with a genealogy of modernity (we are referring to hisclassical work 'The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism' originallypublished in 1920) and he closes this genealogy with the following words:

"In Baxter's view, the care for external goods should only lie onthe shoulders of the saint like a light cloak, which can be thrown aside at anymoment. But fate decreed that the cloak should become an iron cage (...) No oneknows who will live in this cage in the future (...) `specialists without spiritsensualists without heart'"

(Weber, 1968: 181-182)

Fifty years later, Foucault follows the intellectual trail left by Weber andcloses his archaeological stage and the structuralist period of the 'sixtieswith a genealogy of the "disciplinary society" (Foucault, 1975: 209).The Foucauldian genealogy presents some new elements over and above the Weberianone. First, the heavy bars of the cage are not made with iron but with gold.Power is not coercion, it creates. Norm is not restriction, it produces.Secondly, and even more importantly, the object of the disciplinary society isnot a disproportionate instrumental rationality which, step by step, prevailsover the world of values; but rather reflects the negated spirit of thosespecialists and the negated hearts of the sensualists referred in Weber's text.Finally, and crucially, it is in the cage where the soul is produced, through apermanent work over the body:

It would be wrong to say that the soul is an illusion, or an ideologicaleffect. On the contrary, it exists, it has a reality, it is produced permanentlyaround, on, within the body by the functioning of a power that is exercised onthose punished - and, in more general way, on those one supervises, trains andcorrects, over madmen, children at home and at school, the colonized, over thosewho are stuck at a machine and supervised for the rest of their lives.

(Foucault, 1975: 29).

Disciplinary society is an enormous device to produce subjectivities,discipline working upon the body to produce them. In summary, Foucault locatesthe limits of our immediate past and the limits of our mediate present in theschema prefigured by this disciplinary society.

Why discipline?

From Foucault's point of view, the arrival of modernity, the limits of ourpresent, is characterised by three features. Firstly, discipline is not any morea mere anecdotal constriction, it becomes a device: "...thediscipline-mechanism: a functional mechanism that must improve the exercise ofpower by making it lighter, more rapid, more effective, a design of subtlecoercion for a society to come" (Foucault, 1975: 209). There is, here, amove from a discipline as a blocking practice, wholly centred upon its negativefunctions (to stop evil, to fix dis-functional or disturbed collectivities, tobreak off communications) towards a discipline as a mechanism that plays apositive role, and that improves the possible utility of individuals. Secondly,it appears an ubiquity of disciplines. Disciplinary institutions increase, leavetheir marginal site and begin to occupy a more and more extensive surface. Thatwhich was a singular metric, an incidental pattern, is going to become a generalformula:

"Hence, too, the double tendency one sees developing throughout theeighteenth century to increase the number of disciplinary institutions and todiscipline the existing apparatuses"

(Foucault, 1975: 211).

In other words, discipline everywhere and for everybody. Disciplines areorientated not only towards those who are punished, stopping evil is not thesole or even the main goal of disciplinary practices; disciplines proceed to bein the service of good, good for everybody. They make no distinction. Thirdly,there is a nationalisation of the mechanisms of discipline. State institutionstake control of that discipline which was before a punctual practice in theProtestant armies, the Jesuitical schools or the maritime hospitals. Stateappropriates discipline. Organising a centralised police with the mission ofexercising "a permanent, exhaustive, omnipresent surveillance, capable ofmaking all visible..." (Foucault, 1975: 214), is the definitive step for awidening of disciplines that now reach out to the boundaries of the State.

Why society?

Our attention here is upon "the gradual extension of the mechanism ofdiscipline throughout the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, their spreadthroughout the whole social body, the formation of what may be called in generalthe disciplinary society" (Foucault, 1975: 209). We think that what isrelevant and new, and at the same time that which has been less appreciated, inthe Foucauldian expression, "disciplinary society ", is precisely theterm " society ". As Ewald (1990) maintains, the main conclusion todraw from Discipline and Punish is that we do not have to see prison assomething possible because of the generalisation of the disciplinary techniques,instead we have to see prison itself as the institution which offers to modernsociety its authentic image. "Is it surprising that prisons resemblefactories, schools, barracks, hospitals, which all resemble prisons?"(Foucault, 1975: 228). "Disciplinary society " not refers to ageneralised enclosure, only to a generalised diffusion of disciplines.

What is the logic of such a society? Deleuze (1995) has summarized it verywell when he sees the different centres of enclosure as independent variables.The individual successively moves from a closed circle to another. Each onethese circles has its own laws, its own logic. For the individual, there arealways laws to be learnt, a logic that has to be internalised and so on. It is anever ending beginning, after schooling, the barracks begins, after this comesthe factory: these are some of the circles of this tour. Every enclosure is abeginning from zero, a new production of subjectivity. It is not, however, thelogic or the genealogy of this disciplinary society the object of our paper.Rather, what we now go no to propose in the following section is a morphology ofdisciplinary society.

Topography of the disciplinary society

The disciplinary society is mainly a definition of a metric space(specifically an Euclidean space with a linear time). This metric space is ahomogenising space. It concentrates and/or distributes in an ordering manner theelements gathered in it. The diffusion of the disciplines does not entail anydivision or isolation. On the contrary, it implies the creation of an identicalspace all over its parts. Disciplines generate a society with a single languagethat permits communication between all its institutions, that permits aninstitution to be translated to another. This common language for everydisciplinary institution is the norm or that which is normative. Norming jointsup disciplinary institutions and allows translation and communication betweenthem. It enables a society made up of closed circles to be homogeneous by virtueof a full communicability between its elements. It generates an unified socialspace, homogeneous and redundant in all its parts. Ewald expresses very well howsuch norms work: "ordering multiplicities, articulating the whole with itsparts and relating any part with each other" (Ewald, 1989: 165).

A distinction has to be made, however, between norm and discipline. The normis a measure and a way to produce a common standard. Discipline is a practicethat concerns the body and its training, and it is not necessarily normative. Itis the normalisation of the discipline that becomes a characteristic ofmodernity. We are faced with the Rousseau-esque dream: a transparent andhomogeneous society.

Now we want to pay attention to the cornerstone of the disciplinary societynamely, institutions. Whether one thinks of total institutions (Goffman, 1961),or enclosure institutions (Foucault, 1975), it is their architecture thatmatters. Speaking of institutions is equivalent to speaking of buildings.Institution is an ancient term that "denotes and describes a stable balanceon or over a square. The institution has its seat in a building: temple,cathedral, town hall, prison, school, workshop" (Serres, 1995:182). And, ifSerres is right, we can not understand the institution without its plan. Thatis, we can not understand it without looking at it as an architectural space, asa metric space. The building has stable foundations, immobile walls, visibleroofs, corridors to walk along, places to stop at or take a break. Thisgeometric, stable, layout translates the movements of those who are inside intoan inhabiting. We inhabit in geometry (Serres, 1995). We have inhabited theschool, the workshop, the barracks, the factory, the family house and in sodoing, we have been inhabiting institutions.

Institutions, because they are seated in a building, in a plan, in ageometric distribution, evoke, thereby a language of what is closed : avocabulary of the moulds: norms, powers, adjustment, socialisation, history.Defined, planned, built on a metric space, institutions have the capacity togive stability to collectivities and to slow down their history. Architectureallows individuals to be gathered, topography permits their locate on a map, thebuilding bounds time between its walls. The institution makes possible varioushabits to be generated, habits that will survive collectivities. In short,architecture creates a spatio-temporal niche that allows collectivities to begathered around a number of habits.

Institutionalising, that is, is to create conditions to inhabit. It is togeometrize space and time, it is the action of producing a spatio-temporal nichethat can absorb heterogeneous matter and purify it. Institutionalising, refersto a model, or better, to a propellant force towards the inside, one that isperfectly reflected in the prefix "in" of the word "institution".It is not surprising, then, that Foucault has so stressed the importance of themanagement of space in order to produce disciplined individuals:

"Disciplinary space tends to be divided into as many sections asthere are bodies or elements to be distributed. One must eliminate the effectsof imprecise distributions, the uncontrolled disappearance of individuals, theirdiffuse circulation, their unusable and dangerous coagulation; it was a tacticof anti-desertion, anti-vagabondage, anti-concentration. Its aim was toestablish presences and absences, to know where and how to locate individuals,to set up useful communications, to interrupt others, to be able at each momentto supervise the conduct of each individual, to asses it, to judge it, tocalculate its qualities or merits"

(Foucault, 1975:143).

From Institutions to Extitutions

We have talked about institutions as buildings, centring our scope in theprocesses related with enclosure and inhabiting. Institutions have always beenpresent in archeologies, genealogies, histories, and always with a central role.Our thesis is that now they have to share it with other kind of entities. Thesenew entities can resemble the old institutions )- actually, sometimes they havethe same name ) but they need a new vocabulary to conceptualise them. We have tothink of them apart from the building, that is, not as something closed bus assomething open; not as something to inhabit but something to haunt: "For ahouse, habiter (to inhabit); for a forest, hanter (to haunt), to frequent, tohang about: two different states for a similar vital use" (Serres,1994:70). We are going to call these entities, following Serres, ex-titutions.In order to introduce you to them we are going to explain to you how we arrivedat them. The space of the laboratory has allowed us to conceptualiseextitutions.

Everything starts one specific morning. We were in a laboratory of biologyin Barcelona, beginning an ethnographic study. That day everybody was waitingfor the arrival of a very important new machine: a mass spectrometer. When thevan reached the lab. something unexpected happened. They could not get themachine inside. They knew, of course, the machine was very big and heavy. Thatwas the reason why they had asked the supplier to send it in small parcels. Butnobody thought that these small parcels would arrive packed all together in asingle big box. The problem was that the door was not big enough and furthermorethe laboratory lacked a crane to move the box. Some of the researchers that werewatching the scene complained about the architect who had designed the building:"architects don't know how to build a laboratory". That statementposed an interesting question: how should laboratories be built? What was thematter with the space of the laboratory? At that moment, it seemed that thelaboratory was not open enough. Should it always be an open space? That week theethnographic team discussed the nature of the space of the laboratory and itsrelation with the architecture of a building. We actually were taking up again adebate that is central in the birth of the laboratory. We are referring to thepolemic between Hobbes and Boyle that Shapin & Shaffer (1985) summarise soskilfully.

As these authors point out: "What little we do know about Englishexperimental spaces in the middle part of the seventeenth century indicates thattheir status as private or public was intensely debated" (Shapin &Shaffer, 1985:335). We can say, then, that the laboratory is born accompanied bya deep argument about the nature of its space. Whether it was public or privatewas intensely debated. As Shapin and Shaffer(1985) remind us, the firstexperimentalists insisted upon the public nature of their activity. And this isone of the reasons to vindicate the laboratory as a space for experimentation.The laboratory is supposed to be the counterpart of the private, hiddenalchemist's closet. The laboratory is presented by the experimentalist as thespace were matters of fact can be produced. And this is so because it is therethat experimentalists can work with others. The laboratory had to be a placewhere experiments could be performed and where it had to be possible to witnessthem collectively. The presence of witnesses was a crucial aspect of Boyle'sphilosophy. Effectively, it is the testimony of the relevant community whichassures the category of matter of fact to the performed experiments. And "witnessingwas to be a collective act" (Shapin & Shaffer, 1985:56).

But Hobbes pointed out the restriction imposed to the laboratory. From thepoint of view of this philosopher, the laboratory was not that public spaceexperimentalists pretended it was. Hobbes explains that not everyone could enterat Gresham College where the members of the Royal Society came together in orderto perform their experiments. His argument is based on the presence of a "master",a master who decides who could come in and who could not:

"Thus Hobbes disputed the social character of the space theGreshamites said they had created. He said they had a `master' who exercised hisauthority in the constitution of their knowledge; they said they were free andequal men, whose matters of fact mirrored the structure of reality"

(Shapin & Shaffer, 1985:114).

What is, then, the conclusion that Shapin and Shaffer (1985) draw from thedebate between Hobbes and Boyle? From their point of view, the nascentlaboratory is a "public space with restricted access" :

"The Royal Society advertised itself as a `union of eyes, andhands'; the space in which it produced its experimental knowledge was stipulatedto be a public space. It was public in a very precisely defined and veryrigorously policed sense: not everybody could come in; not everybody's testimonywas of equal worth; not everybody was equally able to influence theinstitutional consensus. Nevertheless, what Boyle was proposing, and what RoyalSociety was endorsing, was a crucially important move towards the publicconstitution and validation of knowledge. The contrast was, on the one hand,with the private work of the alchemists, and, on the other, with the individualdictates of the systematic philosopher"

(Shapin & Shaffer, 1985:78).

They clearly believe that Hobbes was right. They even think that this wouldbe a good prescription for present-day laboratories: "many laboratorieshave no legal sanction against a public entry, but they are, as a practicalmatter, open only to 'authorized personnel'" (Shapin and Shaffer,1985:336).

From our point of view, though, both, Hobbes and Boyle, were right, and thisis so because they were talking about two, related, yet different things.Hobbes based his argument in a physical conception of the laboratory. Hobbes wasthinking of a building, something to be closed, an institution. Boyle wasconceptualising something that was beyond a building, he was concerned with acommunity that did not need to be assembled in the same building to act as such.Shapin and Shaffer put us the right track when they say:

"Matters of fact were to be produced in a public space: aparticular physical space in which experiments were collectively performed anddirectly witnessed and an abstract space constituted through virtual witnessing."

(Shapin & Shaffer, 1985:69)

That's right! Boyle was defining the laboratory as an extitution. First, thelaboratory is a virtual space from which everybody can witness an experiment. Itis not just the building, it is a concept that describes an assembly ofheterogeneous elements to produce knowledge. Secondly, the very virtuality ofthis space gives to it the condition of openness and this is why Boyle stressesthe public nature of it. And thirdly, this space, in fact, is a multitude ofspaces. It is a network of laboratories that scientists haunt. As Shapin &Shaffer (1985) show very well in their work, in order to understand theevolution of the air-pump we have to follow experimentalists (Boyle, Huygens,Schott etc.), machines and letters travelling around London, Paris, The Hague,Magdeburg and so on from one centre of pneumatic experimentation to another.It's a continuous haunting describing several single paths. We do not find,then, the habit production we found in institutions. It is impossible to findtwo identical journeys, two identical machines (and that seems to be a bigproblem), two identical experiments.

Directions, points of reference, everything is in a continuous change; thereis no single map to grasp experimentalists' extitutional activities as there wasa single plan to grasp the architecture of the institution. Thus, extitutions gobeyond formal geometry, they need topological thought in order to grasp them. "Ingeometry, I inhabit; topology haunts me" (Serres, 1994, 71). We can say,then, that the laboratory is a tensional space, a battlefield between theinstitutional and the extitutional. This is why we think that both Boyle andHobbes are right, each one of them in one side of the fight. A fight which isstill going on as we could see in the ethnographic story we explained above.Science practice requires buildings such as our laboratory )- a building with aplan, of course )- but these buildings need to be supplemented, to have plentyof holes of different sizes (sometimes very big), as well as bridges,connections and so on. They cannot be those closed circles Deleuze talked aboutto explain institutions. They are knots, nodes, links, bonds, ties, a family ofsynonymous words required to describe and, perhaps, explain a topologicalnature.

Probably some of you will say, after reading this last paragraph, that wealso are taking sides in this struggle. You are right. For us, laboratories cannot be closed spaces. They are closer to extitutions than to institutions. Inthe next section we seek to show you what we consider two other examples ofextitutions.

How extitutions work

In order to illustrate some of the features of an extitution we are going totake as a first example a project for mental health that is about to beimplemented in Catalonia for the Public Health Service. This project is calledPLA DE SERVEIS INDIVIDUALITZAT (PSI), which in English would be something like: Individualised Plan of Services. The PSI is a proposal to organise the processof management of what is called Severe Mental Disorder (SMD) and is born in aclimate of crisis for the conventional attendance system. This is seen as highlyproblematic in terms of the social consequences it involves )- not to mentionbudgetary considerations. If we explore one of the documents elaborated todevelop the project, we can learn that the main goal of the plan is "toadapt the health and social services to the concrete needs of each patient asnearly as possible to their natural pattern, in order to strengthen thecontinuity of attendance".

When the document explains how the necessity for a PSI arose, it states thatit is as a consequence of the move in Catalonia from an Institutional Psychiatryto a Communitarian one in Catalonia, a move that has created an AttendanceNetwork that, for several reasons, is giving a limited answer to the problems ofpatients and their families. So, the document says, "patients that are lesscapable or less prone to ask for help are in risk of remaining out of the system".It is clear, then, that a priority target of the Plan is to avoid a person witha SMD remaining out of the system. The institutional way of guaranteeing this isin process of being dismantled, and what appears instead is a new system, anextitutional one, which takes as a goal this very important characteristic: donot leave a person out of the system.

Very indicative here is the table the document uses to explain the changeimplied by the PSI:

From:

To:

hospital or traditional services

network of communitarian support

illness

damage + malfunction, incapacity, handicap

cure

recovery

Who are the targets of the plan? This is very well defined in the document.A distinction is traced between clinical criteria and social criteria.

Clinical criteria

First, there is a definition of the kind of problems that would be treated:schizophrenic disorder, bipolar disorder, paranoid states, deep depression,obsessive-compulsive disorder, serious personality disorders. Secondly, those tobe targeted should have the following clinical characteristics: a) clinicalseriousness: reality distortion and risk behaviours (auto- or hetero-aggressivity); b) at least two years with these symptoms.

Social criteria

Among the social problematics considered as implicating an interventionthrough the plan, the document cites: a) malfunction; b) functional incapacity(inability to perform a social role); c) dependency; d) manifest familial burdenor absence of family; e) absence of a social network. There is a furtherimportant feature to which to pay attention. The targets of the plan will bethose which have previously used one or more services in a reiterative orextended way. In other words, we can say that the targets are those whopreviously would have been the clients of the institutional enclosure device.The plan is based in which is called "case management". That is,every client is a single case and deserves singular management. There arespecific practice principles for such case management:

  • There should be a single case manager.
  • The locus for attendance is the community.
  • Flexibility in the frequency, length of time and place for the contacts,but firmness in aspects like medication.

Programmes have to get the maximum of individualisation by:

  • Aiming to strengthen capacities for sanity rather than treating thepathology
  • Focusing on achieving the maximum of autonomy for, and responsibility by,the client.

As you can imagine, this programme is presented as a profound cultural andorganisational change. Instead of traditional arrangement of attendance basedin institutional structures and spaces, the PSI poses a processual model whereevery individual case can be seen as a process that passes through each one ofthe institutions involved in the programme. As the document says: "theproposed programmes and their correspondent Individualised Projects can bediagrammed, including the spaces and structures of the service-providers (thename given to hospitals, centres of work, families, centres of rehabilitation,etc.), as ordering horizontal processes which crosses them over from left toright" .

There has to be a person that works as a co-ordinator of each individualisedproject. A co-ordinator covers 20 clients/patients. This person can be a "casemanager" (if is a person independent of the service-providers) or a "keyworker" (if this person occupies a place in one of them). It is veryimportant to note here that this person is not there to impose her/his owncriteria but is charged to get a consensus with the patient and the family.

Having explained the main features of the PSI we think we can assert that weare faced with an extitution. It remains to comment upon what we consider themost salient aspects of it:

1.There is no central building to refer to. The PSI crosses overmany buildings ) Day Hospital, City Council, School, Home, Psychiatric Hospital,Factories, Social Centres ) but it is not in any of them. It is not possibleinhabit in the PSI. Instead of this, we can see how its different elementshaunt, frequent, hang about and are dispersed in an open space.

2.The PSI takes the configuration of a network. In this sense, theconcept of extitutions fits into the framework of Actor-Network Theory analysis.Extitutions are networks simultaneously real, like nature, narrated, likediscourse, and collective, like society (Latour, 1991). Any kind of entity canbe enrolled in the PSI which, at the end, takes the aspect of a heterogeneousconglomeration. There are clients, families, diagnosis, medicaments, hospitals,diseases, social policies, documents like the one we have used, and so on.

3.There is no difference between the inside/outside the PSI. Once wehave accepted that PSI is a network it is nonsensical to look for the inside orthe outside of it (Latour, 1997). Institutions, buildings, have an inside and anoutside, and a boundary. Extitutions, networks, don't have an inside and anoutside, they are only boundary. There is no inside or outside the PSI, thereare only elements that can or cannot be connected with it. Connected with thePSI you can appear as a client, a case manager, a familial, a boss, a diagnosis,an intelligence coefficient. PSI is not a surface capable of geometrisation,rather it is an amalgam of changing connections and associations. What mattersare positions, neighbourhoods, proximities, distances, adherences oraccumulational relationships (Serres, 1994).

Its very existence depends on the work of very specialised figures. We aregoing to call them, following Serres, angels. Effectively, the co-ordinator isan angel that, through his/her movement, haunting, hanging around, connects thedifferent elements of the PSI. Remember one of the coordinator'scharacteristics we cited above: flexibility in the frequency, length of time andplace for the contacts. That is, these angels move in a very unpredictable anddiscontinuous way. Maybe they are going to see a client and, then, in their carthe phone rings and they have to stop and change direction, there is somethingmore important to do: to visit another client, to see the boss. With theirmovements, they weave the local and the global in a kind of entangled knot.Their paths are easier to practice than to describe (Serres, 1994).

We still have one more story. Now we are going to talk about anotherextitution: the Universitat Oberta de Catalunya (UOC), which literally meansOpen University of Catalonia, though it is not exactly an equivalent of theBritish Open University. What makes it particularly interesting is its virtualnature. UOC is a University created around what is called "virtual campus",a campus that is in this virtual space called Internet. As you can read in theinformation located in http://www.uoc.es, the virtual campus is a "set offunctionalities that make possible the interaction between the collectivitiesthat compound the University (students, teachers, managerial staff) without thenecessity to meet in space or time". What we want to stress from thatcitation is its end, "without necessity to meet in space or time".This means that the virtual campus allows every member of the virtual communityremain in its own space and time, forming, thereby, a collectivity that is notonly materially but also spatio-temporally heterogeneous. The virtual campusweaves a fold where different spaces and times are tied together. It is, at thesame time, the maximum of individualisation and the minimum, it, likewise,offers the maximum of globality and the minimum. From their houses, studentscan study with no timetable. At any moment, day or night, students, teachers,consultants, tutors, managerial staff, everybody from their own computer canconnect with the virtual campus. There, they can meet in the virtual bar, theycan read the newspaper, they can participate in discussions, they can askquestions, they can consult books, they can engage in virtual forums of work ordebate and have the opportunity to enter in contact with "a world-wide theworld universitarian, scientific and cultural community". Everybody isaccessible. You can send a message to everybody and everybody can send you amessage.

Contrast UOC with a classical school or university, that is, with aninstitution. We find fluidity rather than stability, topology rather thantopography, dispersion rather than front of concentration, a unified space/timerather than a multiplicity of spaces and times:

"A classical classroom is more or less stable, because it assemblesa given number of people in a place; built with hard matter, as the school, itis an institution, whereas if it is virtual, it fluctuates its spatial figureand the number of people which assembles, in such a way that its plan, alwaysdifferent, is still the same in spite of everything: it is like Teseo's vessel,stable but always new."

(Serres, 1994: 186)

As Serres (1994) observes no architect is needed now, only "designersof circuits, of small and big networks of communication by which associationsare made and unmade" (Serres, 1994:184). Computers and telematic networksare the nature of the system, a "diversified, soft and open system".

Conclusion: Societies of Control

What have we seen with aid of our two examples? From our point of view, bothof them exemplify how, by affecting, locally, each individual, and by tracingseveral direct and inverse paths, from local to global, these networkconfigurations tend to replace the large, old, institutions that wereresponsible for global regulation: Schools, Factories, State and so on (Serres,1994) If Serres is right and, furthermore, if we accept the oft-pronouncedcrises of institutionalisation, then we have also to admit also that Deleuzetoo(1995) is right when he talks about the disciplinary society, so well drawnby Foucault, as something we must locate in our past.

It is probably premature to risk a new label to describe our emergentpresent. Nevertheless, it seems reasonable to propose that we can find, in ourpresent, a mixture of entities, some of them resembling the old institutions andsome others nearer of what we have called extitutions. And when we pay attentionto these new entities, we can see that some of their characteristics (asdescribed above) would fit very well in the scenario drawn by Deleuze (1995)when he suggests the name "societies of control" to refer our present.Summing up, such societies present the following features:

  • control comes to substitute for discipline;
  • control is exercised "in the open air" it does not need anenclosure base;
  • whereas discipline produced individuals, control modulates them;
  • modulation is a changing and fluctuating activity;
  • control is manifested as short-term exercise, replaced by other suchexercises in quick rotation, thereby it also is continuous ) whereasdiscipline was long lasting , infinite and uncontinuous.

Taken as a whole we can contemplate extitutions as closer to societies ofcontrol than to a disciplinary society. In the extitutions there is nodiscipline, there are no buildings to enclose, there are no specific moulds toproduce subjects. Instead of this we have seen mechanisms of control, open andchanging systems, modulation activity, and local and short term practices in acontinuous weaving of the global.

E-mail: ilps9@cc.uab.es

References

Deleuze, G. (1995) Conversaciones. Valencia: Pre-Textos

Foucault, M. (1975) Discipline and Punish. The Birth of the Prison. London:Penguin Books, 1977.

Ewald, F. (1989) Un poder sin un afuera. In E. Balbier et al. MichelFoucault. Filósofo. Barcelona: Gedisa, 1990.

Goffman, E. (1961) Internados. Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1992.

Latour, B. (1991) We have never been modern. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf,1993.

Latour, B. (1997) On Actor-Network Theory. A Few Clarifications. Publishedby the

Centre for Social Theory and Technology, Keele University at:

http://www.keele.ac.uk/depts/stt/stt/ant/latour.htm.

Serres, M (1994) Atlas. Madrid: C tedra, 1995.

Shapin, S. & Shaffer, S. (1985) Leviathan and the Air-Pump. Hobbes,Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

Weber, M. (1930) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. London:Unwin University Books, 1968.

1

 

especiales
despiertos
collagencia
desenrredes
verbigracia
wequito
archivos

links

sitio
 
inicio
webmaster
editorial|opinion|especiales|despiertos|galgeria|desenrredes|links|bejuco|sitio |inicio