The Pitfalls of
Universal Jurisdiction
by Henry Kissinger
Foreign Affairs,
July / August 2001
RISKING JUDICIAL TYRANNY
In less than a decade, an
unprecedented movement has emerged to submit international politics to judicial
procedures. It has spread with extraordinary speed and has not been subjected
to systematic debate, partly because of the intimidating passion of its
advocates. To be sure, human rights violations, war crimes, genocide, and
torture have so disgraced the modern age and in such a variety of places that
the effort to interpose legal norms to prevent or punish such outrages does
credit to its advocates. The danger lies in pushing the effort to extremes that
risk substituting the tyranny of judges for that of governments; historically,
the dictatorship of the virtuous has often led to inquisitions and even
witch-hunts.
The doctrine of universal
jurisdiction asserts that some crimes are so heinous that their perpetrators
should not escape justice by invoking doctrines of sovereign immunity or the
sacrosanct nature of national frontiers. Two specific approaches to achieve
this goal have emerged recently. The first seeks to apply the procedures of
domestic criminal justice to violations of universal standards, some of which
are embodied in United Nations conventions, by authorizing national prosecutors
to bring offenders into their jurisdictions through extradition from third
countries. The second approach is the International Criminal Court (ICC), the
founding treaty for which was created by a conference in Rome in July 1998 and
signed by 95 states, including most European countries. It has already been
ratified by 3o nations and will go into effect when the total reaches 60. On
December 31, 2000, President Bill Clinton signed the ICC treaty with only hours
to spare before the cutoff date. But he indicated that he would neither submit
it for Senate approval nor recommend that his successor do so while the treaty
remains in its present form.
The very concept of universal
jurisdiction is of recent vintage. The sixth edition of Black's Law Dictionary,
published in 1990, does not contain even an entry for the term. The closest
analogous concept listed is hostes humani generis ("enemies of the human
race"). Until recently, the latter term has been applied to pirates,
hijackers, and similar outlaws whose crimes were typically committed outside
the territory of any state. The notion that heads of state and senior public officials
should have the same standing as outlaws before the bar of justice is quite
new.
In the aftermath of the
Holocaust and the many atrocities committed since, major efforts have been made
to find a judicial standard to deal with such catastrophes: the Nuremberg
trials of 1945-46, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1948, the
genocide convention of 1948, and the anti-torture convention of 1988. The Final
Act of the Conference on Security and Cooperation in Europe, signed in Helsinki
in 1975 by President Gerald Ford on behalf of the United States, obligated the
35 signatory nations to observe certain stated human rights, subjecting
violators to the pressures by which foreign policy commitments are generally
sustained. In the hands of courageous groups in Eastern Europe, the Final Act
became one of several weapons by which communist rule was delegitimized and
eventually undermined. In the 1990S, international tribunals to punish crimes
committed in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda, established ad hoc by the U.N.
Security Council, have sought to provide a system of accountability for
specific regions ravaged by arbitrary violence.
But none of these steps was
conceived at the time as instituting a "universal jurisdiction." It
is unlikely that any of the signatories of either the U.N. conventions or the
Helsinki Final Act thought it possible that national judges would use them as a
basis for extradition requests regarding alleged crimes committed outside their
jurisdictions. The drafters almost certainly believed that they were stating
general principles, not laws that would be enforced by national courts. For
example, Eleanor Roosevelt, one of the drafters of the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights, referred to it as a "common standard." As one of the
negotiators of the Final Act of the Helsinki conference, I can affirm that the
administration I represented considered it primarily a diplomatic weapon to use
to thwart the communists' attempts to pressure the Soviet and captive peoples.
Even with respect to binding undertakings such as the genocide convention, it
was never thought that they would subject past and future leaders of one nation
to prosecution by the national magistrates of another state where the
violations had not occurred. Nor, until recently, was it argued that the
various U.N. declarations subjected past and future leaders to the possibility
of prosecution by national magistrates of third countries without either due
process safeguards or institutional restraints.
Yet this is in essence the
precedent that was set by the 1998 British detention of former Chilean
President Augusto Pinochet as the result of an extradition request by a Spanish
judge seeking to try Pinochet for crimes committed against Spaniards on Chilean
soil. For advocates of universal jurisdiction, that detention-lasting more than
16 months- was a landmark establishing a just principle. But any universal
system should contain procedures not only to punish the wicked but also to
constrain the righteous. It must not allow legal principles to be used as
weapons to settle political scores. Questions such as these must therefore be
answered: What legal norms are being applied? What are the rules of evidence?
What safeguards exist for the defendant? And how will prosecutions affect other
fundamental foreign policy objectives and interests?
A DANGEROUS PRECEDENT
It is decidedly unfashionable
to express any degree of skepticism about the way the Pinochet case was
handled. For almost all the parties of the European left, Augusto Pinochet is
the incarnation of a right-wing assault on democracy because he led a coup
d'etat against an elected leader. At the time, others, including the leaders of
Chile's democratic parties, viewed Salvador Allende as a radical Marxist
ideologue bent on imposing a Castro-style dictatorship with the aid of
Cuban-trained militias and Cuban weapons. This was why the leaders of Chile's
democratic parties publicly welcomed-yes, welcomed-Allende's overthrow. (They
changed their attitude only after the junta brutally maintained its autocratic
rule far longer than was warranted by the invocation of an emergency.)
Disapproval of the Allende
regime does not exonerate those who perpetrated systematic human rights abuses
after it was overthrown. But neither should the applicability of universal
jurisdiction as a policy be determined by one's view of the political history
of Chile.
The world must respect Chile's
own attempt to come to terms with its brutal past.
The appropriate solution was
arrived at in August 2000 when the Chilean Supreme Court withdrew Pinochet's
senatorial immunity, making it possible to deal with the charges against him in
the courts of the country most competent to judge this history and to relate
its decisions to the stability and vitality of its democratic institutions.
On November 25, 1998, the
judiciary committee of the British House of Lords (the United Kingdom's supreme
court) concluded that "international law has made it plain that certain
types of conduct ... are not acceptable conduct on the part of anyone."
But that principle did not oblige the lords to endow a Spanish magistrate-and
presumably other magistrates elsewhere in the world-with the authority to
enforce it in a country where the accused had committed no crime, and then to
cause the restraint of the accused for 16 months in yet another country in
which he was equally a stranger. It could have held that Chile, or an
international tribunal specifically established for crimes committed in Chile
on the model of the courts set up for heinous crimes in the former Yugoslavia
and Rwanda, was the appropriate forum.
The unprecedented and sweeping
interpretation of international law in Ex parte Pinochet would arm any
magistrate anywhere in the world with the power to demand extradition,
substituting the magistrate's own judgment for the reconciliation procedures of
even incontestably democratic societies where alleged violations of human
rights may have occurred. It would also subject the accused to the criminal
procedures of the magistrate's country, with a legal system that may be
unfamiliar to the defendant and that would force the defendant to bring
evidence and witnesses from long distances. Such a system goes far beyond the
explicit and limited mandates established by the U.N. Security Council for the
tribunals covering war crimes in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda as well as
the one being negotiated for Cambodia.
Perhaps the most important
issue is the relationship of universal jurisdiction to national reconciliation
procedures set up by new democratic governments to deal with their countries'
questionable pasts. One would have thought that a Spanish magistrate would have
been sensitive to the incongruity of a request by Spain, itself haunted by
transgressions committed during the Spanish Civil War and the regime of General
Francisco Franco, to try in Spanish courts alleged crimes against humanity
committed elsewhere.
The decision of post-Franco
Spain to avoid wholesale criminal trials for the human rights violations of the
recent past was designed explicitly to foster a process of national
reconciliation that undoubtedly contributed much to the present vigor of
Spanish democracy. Why should Chile's attempt at national reconciliation not
have been given the same opportunity? Should any outside group dissatisfied
with the reconciliation procedures of, say, South Africa be free to challenge
them in their own national courts or those of third countries?
It is an important principle
that those who commit war crimes or systematically violate human rights should
be held accountable. But the consolidation of law, domestic peace, and
representative government in a nation struggling to come to terms with a brutal
past has a claim as well. The instinct to punish must be related, as in every
constitutional democratic political structure, to a system of checks and
balances that includes other elements critical to the survival and expansion of
democracy.
Another grave issue is the use
in such cases of extradition procedures designed for ordinary criminals. If the
Pinochet case becomes a precedent, magistrates anywhere will be in a position
to put forward an extradition request without warning to the accused and
regardless of the policies the accused's country might already have in place
for dealing with the charges. The country from which extradition is requested
then faces a seemingly technical legal decision that, in fact, amounts to the
exercise of political discretion-whether to entertain the claim or not.
Once extradition procedures are
in train, they develop a momentum of their own. The accused is not allowed to
challenge the substantive merit of the case and instead is confined to
procedural issues: that there was, say, some technical flaw in the extradition
request, that the judicial system of the requesting country is incapable of
providing a fair hearing, or that the crime for which the extradition is sought
is not treated as a crime in the country from which extradition has been
requested-thereby conceding much of the merit of the charge. Meanwhile, while
these claims are being considered by the judicial system of the country from
which extradition is sought, the accused remains in some form of detention,
possibly for years. Such procedures provide an opportunity for political
harassment long before the accused is in a position to present any defense. It
would be ironic if a doctrine designed to transcend the political process turns
into a means to pursue political enemies rather than universal justice.
The Pinochet precedent, if
literally applied, would permit the two sides in the Arab-Israeli conflict, or
those in any other passionate international controversy, to project their
battles into the various national courts by pursuing adversaries with
extradition requests. When discretion on what crimes are subject to universal
jurisdiction and whom to prosecute is left to national prosecutors, the scope
for arbitrariness is wide indeed. So far, universal jurisdiction has involved
the prosecution of one fashionably reviled man of the right while scores of East
European communist leaders-not to speak of Caribbean, Middle Eastern, or
African leaders who inflicted their own full measures of torture and
suffering-have not had to face similar prosecutions.
Some will argue that a double
standard does not excuse violations of international law and that it is better
to bring one malefactor to justice than to grant immunity to all. This is not
an argument permitted in the domestic jurisdictions of many democracies-in
Canada, for example, a charge can be thrown out of court merely by showing that
a prosecution has been selective enough to amount to an abuse of process. In
any case, a universal standard of justice should not be based on the
proposition that a just end warrants unjust means, or that political fashion
trumps fair judicial procedures.
AN INDISCRIMINATE COURT
The ideological supporters of
universal jurisdiction also provide much of the intellectual compass for the
emerging International Criminal Court. Their goal is to criminalize certain
types of military and political actions and thereby bring about a more humane
conduct of international relations. To the extent that the ICC replaces the
claim of national judges to universal jurisdiction, it greatly improves the
state of international law. And, in time, it may be possible to negotiate.
At any future time, U.S.
officials involved in the NATO air campaign in Kosovo could face international
prosecution.
Modifications of the present
statute to make the ICC more compatible with U.S. constitutional practice. But
in its present form of assigning the ultimate dilemmas of international
politics to unelected jurists-and to an international judiciary at that-it
represents such a fundamental change in U.S. constitutional practice that a
full national debate and the full participation of Congress are imperative.
Such a momentous revolution should not come about by tacit acquiescence in the
decision of the House of Lords or by dealing with the ICC issue through a
strategy of improving specific clauses rather than as a fundamental issue of
principle.
The doctrine of universal
jurisdiction is based on the proposition that the individuals or cases subject
to it have been clearly identified. In some instances, especially those based
on Nuremberg precedents, the definition of who can be prosecuted in an
international court and in what circumstances is self-evident. But many issues
are much more vague and depend on an understanding of the historical and
political context. It is this fuzziness that risks arbitrariness on the part of
prosecutors and judges years after the event and that became apparent with
respect to existing tribunals.
For example, can any leader of
the United States or of another country be hauled before international
tribunals established for other purposes? This is precisely what Amnesty
International implied when, in the summer of 1999, it supported a
"complaint" by a group of European and Canadian law professors to
Louise Arbour, then the prosecutor of the International Criminal Tribunal for
the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY). The complaint alleged that crimes against
humanity had been committed during the NATO air campaign in Kosovo. Arbour
ordered an internal staff review, thereby implying that she did have
jurisdiction if such violations could, in fact, be demonstrated. Her successor,
Carla Del Ponte, in the end declined to indict any NATO official because of a
general inability "to pinpoint individual responsibilities," thereby
implying anew that the court had jurisdiction over NATO and American leaders in
the Balkans and would have issued an indictment had it been able to identify
the particular leaders allegedly involved.
Most Americans would be amazed
to learn that the ICTY, created at U.S. behest in 1993 to deal with Balkan war
criminals, had asserted a right to investigate U.S. political and military
leaders for allegedly criminal conduct-and for the indefinite future, since no
statute of limitations applies. Though the ICTY prosecutor chose not to pursue
the charge-on the ambiguous ground of an inability to collect evidence-some
national prosecutor may wish later to take up the matter as a valid subject for
universal jurisdiction.
The pressures to achieve the
widest scope for the doctrine of universal jurisdiction were demonstrated as
well by a suit before the European Court of Human Rights in June 2000 by
families of Argentine sailors who died in the sinking of the Argentine cruiser
General Belgano during the Falklands War. The concept of universal jurisdiction
has moved from judging alleged political crimes against humanity to
second-guessing, 18 years after the event, military operations in which neither
civilians nor civilian targets were involved.
Distrusting national
governments, many of the advocates of universal jurisdiction seek to place
politicians under the supervision of magistrates and the judicial system. But
prosecutorial discretion without accountability is precisely one of the flaws
of the International Criminal Court. Definitions of the relevant crimes are
vague and highly susceptible to politicized application. Defendants will not
enjoy due process as understood in the United States. Any signatory state has
the right to trigger an investigation. As the U.S. experience with the special
prosecutors investigating the executive branch shows, such a procedure is
likely to develop its own momentum without time limits and can turn into an
instrument of political warfare. And the extraordinary attempt of the ICC to
assert jurisdiction over Americans even in the absence of U.S. accession to the
treaty has already triggered legislation in Congress to resist it.
The independent prosecutor of
the ICC has the power to issue indictments, subject to review only by a panel
of three judges. According to the Rome statute, the Security Council has the
right to quash any indictment. But since revoking an indictment is subject to
the veto of any permanent Security Council member, and since the prosecutor is
unlikely to issue an indictment without the backing of at least one permanent
member of the Security Council, he or she has virtually unlimited discretion in
practice. Another provision permits the country whose citizen is accused to
take over the investigation and trial. But the ICC retains the ultimate
authority on whether that function has been adequately exercised and, if it
finds it has not, the ICC can reassert jurisdiction. While these procedures are
taking place, which may take years, the accused will be under some restraint
and certainly under grave public shadow.
The advocates of universal
jurisdiction argue that the state is the basic cause of war and cannot be
trusted to deliver justice. If law replaced politics, peace and justice would
prevail. But even a cursory examination of history shows that there is no evidence
to support such a theory. The role of the statesman is to choose the best
option when seeking to advance peace and justice, realizing that there is
frequently a tension between the two and that any reconciliation is likely to
be partial. The choice, however, is not simply between universal and national
jurisdictions.
MODEST PROPOSALS
The precedent set by
international tribunals established to deal with situations where the enormity
of the crime is evident and the local judicial system is clearly incapable of
administering justice, as in the former Yugoslavia and Rwanda, have shown that
it is possible to punish without removing from the process all political
judgment and experience. In time, it may be possible to renegotiate the ICC
statute to avoid its shortcomings and dangers. Until then, the United States
should go no further toward a more formal system than one containing the
following three provisions. First, the U.N. Security Council would create a
Human Rights Commission or a special subcommittee to report whenever systematic
human rights violations seem to warrant judicial action. Second, when the
government under which the alleged crime occurred is not authentically
representative, or where the domestic judicial system is incapable of sitting
in judgment on the crime, the Security Council would set up an ad hoc
international tribunal on the model of those of the former Yugoslavia or
Rwanda. And third, the procedures for these international tribunals as well as
the scope of the prosecution should be precisely defined by the Security
Council, and the accused should be entitled to the due process safeguards
accorded in common jurisdictions.
In this manner, internationally
agreed procedures to deal with war crimes, genocide, or other crimes against
humanity could become institutionalized. Furthermore, the one-sidedness of the
current pursuit of universal jurisdiction would be avoided. This pursuit could
threaten the very purpose for which the concept has been developed. In the end,
an excessive reliance on universal jurisdiction may undermine the political
will to sustain the humane norms of international behavior so necessary to
temper the violent times in which we live.
HENRY A. KISSINGER, Chairman of Kissinger Associates,
Inc., is a former Secretary of State and National Security Adviser. This essay
is adapted from his latest book, Does America Need a Foreign Policy? Toward a
Diplomacy for the 2lst Century.