[Back to FLEEDING main page]  [Back to PERF main page]

On this page:

               {www.ritual.org}

See also:  [artist as shaman]


Invariance, Evolution, and Act

In this section, i begin to explore the concepts of various kinds of acts. The (existing) terminology seems a bit muddled. So, hopefully i can delve into it and shed a bit of 21st century light upon it. (After all, i am (ahem) some-what intellegent, and if *i* am having difficulty sorting it all out, how can the purely practising artist hope to incorporate these important ideas into their work -- not only from a theoretical POV, but from a very down-to-earth way of *thinking* about the work and the aritst, and of course the socieity/time/planet/etc that we find ourselves embedded into, and more importantly: A part of the main as John Donne put it. Perhaps *we* are the bell ringer of whom he refers to: "Do not send to ask for whom the bell tolls; it tolls for thee". [Ref: "The Tolling Bell; an elegy" by the poet John Donne ??date?? ??link??] For indeed as Smith concluded in his article [P.481] It is in ritual space that the hunter can relate himself properly to animals which are both "good to eat" and "good to think". I take this to be of the two ways of understanding: Contemplative and Reflective. Indeed, i would go so far as to posit: Contemplative The Act Reflective pre-liminal liminal post-liminal future-possible the present past-subjunctive This is an attempt to tie the variety of terms together. And thus, what i have learned from these two readins is comprised in this new way of my own thinking; ie, thus, i too am transformed - the writer transforms the reader and the "message" sent is both knowledge and understanding as well as (if the reader is open-minded) seed for imagination. Thus, my primary thesis would run something like this: 1) The oath that is sworn is indeed an act and it is indeed *just* words. As "just words, the oath ties the oath-maker in the present-then (pre-liminal) to some future action (the liminal). The *extent* to which this oath is to have meaning and thus require the oath-maker to full-fill the promise of the oath is tied to *ritual*. If the oath-maker performs the ritual, then she/he/ne is *morally* required to full-fill. I would go further (differing from Rappaport) that the ritual does *not* have to be performed publically. If the oath-maker takes the oath in what Sartre would refer to as "in good fatih", then the oath (for the oath-maker) is as meaningfull and contractually obligatory as if it were made in front of the community. This extends Rappaport's idea: To say that ritual is the basic social act must be to say that it is in some sense moral, for the social subsumes the moral. ... [ellison, mine] It might even be argued that the violation of obligation is the fundamental immoral act. [as quoted in Grimes, P. 435] {ref} Thus, this becomes (in the privately sworn oath) a private reproach or a privat act of immorality if the oath is NOT full-filled. Thus, the sworn oath (or other ritual of commitment to act in the future) is just that: a future-possible action: That is, future-indicative; ie, I *will* come to your aid, I *will* do such and so, etc. 2) Contrasting this with the liminal event/act/time itself. The *actual* act is performed. This either does or does not full-fill the oath in the pre-liminal state of the ritual. Note that in this state, we are in what Rappaport calls the "performative utterances" which are "factive". Thus (in his example) if i name the ship "The Queen Elisabeth" then the ship IS named by that utterance. This, devolves to what i would refer to as "associated co-ercive oaths"; ie, an oath which is formally undertaken and then observed -- acted out/full-filled/etc. Note that we can not insure that we can full-fill the oath. Indeed, we might swear to give our lives to save the king's, but we might be killed in the performative present; ie, the liminal "now". 3) Finally, after the event, as remarked earlier by the quote from rappaport. We are in the reflective post-liminal state. And in retrospect/reflection/musing/etc we enter the "i shouod have done this", and other such after-the-fact thoughts. This of course *can* lead to a different plan of action for the future, and hence to a different way of thinking about even the *same* oath/action/result at some point in the future.

A Brief Comparison

I will now consider three aspects of ritual and how Rappaport and Smith differ in their approaches. There are no "right or wrong" answers. We wish to understand the complex and intricate natures of riutal that we often take for granted, and as such over-look or even more dangerously: mis-interpret. The concept of invariance is the idea that the ritual (or at least certain parts of it) can not and should not vary. This is to insure that the "mile posts" of the ritual remain constant, recongnisable and meaningful. The reason that this imporatant is that without the explicitly stated/acted/etc portions of the ritual the underlying metaphore of the ritual (and hence the meaning/relevance/symbolism/etc of the ritual, in-toto) becomes lost or at the very least garbled. The next aspect investigated is the concept of the act itself. To a certain extent, even the *intention* to perform a ritual is in itself the ritual. Thus, if i say "i should perform the rain danse", then this calls to mind the facts of the *actual* rain danse. Thus, this "future-possible" oath (taken in the subjunctive) has a power *on-par* with the performance of the ritual itself. For example, in a certain tribe in the Hebredes (as i recall) there is a ritually planted tree that ends a feud between two tribes. At some point (when the population of the tribes has over-grown the ability of the environment to support them), people start saying "some one ought to pull up that tree". These *potential/subjunctive/future-possible* statements open the door to the ritual and form a coercive beginning of the ritual which (during the liminal stage) cause the slaughter of many people in both of the tribes. Finally, in terms of the *adaptation* of the ritual; ie, evolution. This clearly falls into the category as Hegel would say: Thesis --> creates its anti-pode: anti-thesis and the "fall out" from the conflict of these two creates Thesis x Antithesis --> syn-thesis (new thesis) Thus, the failings of the current ritual in handling new input (usually from an external influence, or some unique event in the society's experience) -- leads to a changing of the ritual. Rappaport focuses quite a bit on *liturgical* ritual which almost by definition can *not* change.

Invariance vs Non-Invariance

We now look at two diametrically opposed forces in any system: Invariance vs Evolution. The concept of invariance is to maintain the status quo and thus assure stability in the society -- even if that stability consists of very dynamic changes in behaviour, etc. Evolution is of course how a system (in this case a society) adapts to changes in the environment (both internal and external). From one point of view: "Stay the course or risk chaos" vs "Evolve or die". On the one hand Rappaport emphasizes how the ritual is repetitive and invariant. And the nature of the *message* transmitted (he doesn't make it clear if there is a one-to-one (invariant) relationship between the message and the signals by which it is transmitted. Thus, the cannonial message (invariant) does not necessarily reflect the signals used to encode it. Frankly, i'm reading between the lines here a bit, since as Rapport states: The [the messages] are found by participants already encoded in the liturgy. Since these messages are more or less invariant, obviously they can not in themselves reflect the transmittter's contemporary state. For instance, the *order* of the Roman mass does not, [emph mine] in itself, express antyhing about the current states of those perofrming it. In recognition of the regularity, propriety, and appartent durability and immutability of these messages, I shall refer to them as "canonical". We contrast this with Smtith's view that the rituals are almost *always* mutable. In fact, he begins his essay with: I should liie to begin tis essay with one such coincicdecne [ie, similar to Joseph Campbell's encoutnring the same sorts of fold stories in various cultures witn no possibility of common origin] and juxtapose two texts separated in time by eighteen centuries. The one is from Kafka, the other from Plutarch. Leopards break into the temple and drink the sacrificial challices dry; this occurs repeatedly, again and again; finally it can be reckoned on beforehand and becomes part of the ceremony. [Local note 1: F. Kafka, "Reflections on Sin, Hope, and the True Way", in Kafka: The Great Wall of China, (New Yorkk, 1970, P.165] At Athens, Lysimache, the priestess of Athene Polias, when asked for a drink by the mule drivers who had transported the sacred vellses, replied, "No, for I fear it will get into the ritual." [Local note 2: Plutarch De vitioso Pudore (ca. 534CE0] This indicates the two diametrically oppsing views of ritual: Immutability vs. evolution. In either case, the *meaning* of the various acts that are part of the ritual (and the meaning of the ritual in total) must be known by the particiapants. Otherwise the ritual becomes "mere" pastiche of the original purpose and meaning of the ritual. One of the clearest examples of this is the ritual of saying "Bless you" when some one sneezes. Originally, there was actually fear that the person would be sneezing out the very "breath of their soul" and than un-less blessed, they could imperile their eternal soul. These days, the response is so rigidly embodied that we respond without thinking. Note that the *act* of the tirual (saying "bless you") still remains, although the purpose has been all but lost. Thus, this immutable ritual has *not* evolved, but since the meanings of the symbols has been lost it has become pastiche and thus meaningless. Although, i should say that now the act of saying "bless you" has retained one aspect of its original weight: It shows that the person saying "bless you" not only acknowledges the existence of the other person, but is (to some extent at least) in sympathy with them. I would thus maintain that unless the meaning of the ritual is maintained then the ghost of the ritual remains and thus looses any effectiveness that it might have had. Thus, the only invariant is variance.

Pledge: Promise of Future Action

Another difference between Rappaport and Smith is the concept of "pledge". For Rappaport, the pledge is not just spoken, but is in and of itsefl and act. For example: By dancing at a kaiko a Maring man singals his *pledge* to help his hosts in warefare. Dancing signals [emph mine] a pledge becasue it is itself a pledging. As such ...it [ellision in original] indicates rather than merely symbolises the pledge with which it is "identififed"; ie, made identical. Now I wish to emphasise that "to pledge" is not merely to say something. A pledge is an act. [Grims, P.430] This clearly sets the pledge above just words (obviously). But, it further asserts (or so i would maintain) that the pledge is almost as "good as" the act. Indeed, Rappaport goes on for several more paragrpahs about other pledges; eg, "We declare war", "I swear to tell the truth", etc. It should be obvious that if the head of state declared war on another country, then it wouldn't matter if they attacked or not; steps would be set in process for war. This actually goes back to the code of the Samurai in that even if two camps are declared in a state of war, if one of one camp acts honorably to defend one of the other camp's members when attacked by a third party (or nature), then this is seen as a "higher calling" and thus, the act (acting honorably) takes precedence over the pledge (we are sworn enemies to the death). These kinds of juxtapositions are in fact inevitable in any sufficiently advanced system of behaviour. On the other hand, Smith [Grimes, P.478] clearly indicates that the pledge can in fact be a promise and nothing more. he recounts the killing reitual of the Yakuts in that hunter must awake the bear before he attacks it, or esle the hunter will be killed in his sleep by bears. Indeed, the ritual is to openly greet the bear honoring it, and *pledging* to kill it; ie, the bear is there to be killed as a conscious act of being and the hunter pledges to keep his end of the bargain and perform the killing. Should the bear decide to leave and not take part in the hunt, then it leaves the pledge un-full-filled. It should be noted that as part of the ritual is that the hunter tells the bear that he will not chace after it, that the bear should come and meet its death. Thus, (at least in this case), Smith maintains that the pledge is *not* above the act -- as opposed Rapport who (at least in the case sited) that the pledge is at par with or possibly even above the act. And yet, on the third hand, one could argue that both Rappaport and Smith vary only in *degree* and are not so diametrically opposed as one might suggest. To counter Rapport, we need only look at the fake threats that are often given to *avoid* conflict, thus the pledge becomes empty -- or at the very least "as-yet un-full-filled". To counter Smith, we can look at the same "fake oaths" as they esculate. In this case, if the oaths esculate to a certain point, then conflict *will* occur. Thus, i would say that although of different points of view, Rapporat and Smith are both describing the same elephant. What then are we to make of oaths, pledges, threats, etc in general? In the case of human viz-a-vis human, the signals sent back and forth must be mutally understood. Otherwise, it devolves to the human vz-a-vis animal model. For example, if two different tribes encounter each other for the first time and use the methods of pledge, threat, etc that they are each used to, then it is almost inevitable that the signals will be mis-interpreted. On the other hand, in dealing with human viz-a-vis animal. It is unlikely that the animal (eg, the bear) understands a real pledge from a symbolic one. In the example given, i would assume that the Yakut issuing the pledge would make it in such a manner that the bear would understand the *tone* of voice. I think that at least *that* much of the message could be carried across the chasm between man and bear. If the pledge given is merely symbolic (eg, before the hunt begins, and there is little chance that the bear would hear the pledge), then it falls to the realm of the spiritual rather than the material. This brings us to another point of interest: The Material vs. Spiritual. Or more properly "symbolic" vs "manifest" -- or however, you want to put it. Prayers given in private are usually considered to be indirect in that they are "hoped for" and may not come to pass; ie, they may not become manifested, and thus reamin spiritual/symbolic. Prayers when given in public although symbolic can in fact become manifest. For example, the "pep talk" that a coach gives before a game is meant to co-erce the team to play to win. One of the best examples of this (in literature) occurs in Mark Twain's "The War Prayer" in which after a preachers stirring prayer for victory of their troops, an angel from on high comes to answer it. But, first wishes to clarify the request by indicating the "other side" of the praryer; eg, that you wish for your sons to return home alive hides the "other prayer" the the other side's sons will die horribly in battle, etc. Thus, even the symbolic pledge has an *implied* manifest partner. Of the manifest pledge, there is clearly indicated some sort of "back drop" within which it operates. As such, it should be clear that every manifest pledge carries with it an *implied* spiritual pledge. Thus, to Rapport, i would say that even the most manifest pledge does not necessarily manifest itself, but that as Smith points out, that the spirtual message is given (and heard) by the issuer. Whether the pledge has an effect depends more on belief and emotion than any pure physics of the situation. Yes, i know i'm dancing dangerously on the rather brittle edges between: ontology (how does each "item" work, and what are their relationships between the issuer of the pledge, the pledge itself, and the receiver of the pledge - even if the bear isn't present when the oath is given) phenomenology (if the bear doesn't hear the oath, then does it still go "gladly to its death"?) epistimolgy (do the spiritual/unknowable/in-direct actions/oaths, etc have any *physical* effect on the situation? Can they?) But one fact remains: The issuer of the pledge *knows* that s/he/ne has made a pledge and when the *event* that the pledge is about comes up: How does that affect their state of being? And of course it was at this point that the left-leaning, and much hobbled would-be philosopher's befuddled brain knew that it was out of its depth and the philsopher (of whom the brain belonged to) stepped off of his soap box and fell face first into a very recently depositied load of horse hockey and then night fell, and there was a thunderclap, and suddently it was thursday (for the third time that week)... -- Frank.

References

(tips towel to [
ed.usa.edu] [in the new way] "Readings in Ritual Studies" by Ronald L. Grimes ISBN 0.02.347253.7, LCCN BL'600.R453'1996, (Prentice-Hall, 1996, Upper Saddle River, New Jersey, Terra).

Bibilography

[in the way of tradition] Bahti, T. (1971). Southwestern Indian Ceremonials. Las Vegas, Nevada: KC Publications. Bruchac, J. (1994). A Boy Called Slow. New York, NY: Philomel Books Grimes, Ronald L. (1996) Readings in Ritual Studies. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prenctice-Hall. Lutske, H. (1986). The Book of Jewish Customs. Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson Inc. Rappaport, Roy A. [Grimes: Pp.427-440] The Obvious Aspects of Ritual. Grimes: OpCit. Smith, Johnathon Z. [Grimes, P.478-481].The Bare Facts of Ritual. Grimes: OpCit. Tiersky, E. & M. (1975). Customs and Institutions. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall Regents. Van Gennep, A. (1960). The Rites of Passage. Chicago, Ill: The University of Chicago Press. "Rite of Passage." The World Book Encyclopedia. 1989 ed. Slave Narratives-Part 3. Vol. 12 St. Claire Shores, Michigan: Scholarly Press, Inc., 1976. {use the BACK button on your browser if needed to return to the text}

www.ritual.org

Mirrored from... [
www.ritual.org">] BEGIN BLOCK QUOTE Oh don't you know? We could have changed the world When we were young And the world was ours But who were we? Auch die Natur wartet auf die Revolution (Nature, too, Awaits the Revolution) [synopsis by the original author] The erotic energy of nature - an energy which is there to be liberated; nature, too, awaits the revolution! (Herbert Marcuse, Counter-Revolution and Revolt) - how can this sentence be rationally reconstructed? The paper proposes to define nature as the aggregate of all self-organizing objects of physics. This establishes a formal teleology which enables us to attribute "intention" to nature without a recourse to metaphysics: anything that turns self-organization into self-destruction is "against nature's intention" because it opposes the very meaning of nature. There are several levels of self-organization in nature, the two highest being sexuality and mind. In contrast to lower levels of self-organization, sexuality "plots" and optimizes the information for catalytic self-production by combining two sets of data before realizing their inherent structures. Mind is an even higher level of self-organization in that intentional self-production doesn't need a physiological substrate to represent the plotted data. As a somatic and at the same time self-conscious being, man is located amidst the two levels mentioned above. If you call the synthesis of sexuality and mind erotic, it can thus be said that the main principle of self-organization of man is erotic. Since sexuality and mind are the highest forms of self-organization we know of, we can call nature's potential for self-organization as a whole the erotic energy of nature. Tensions between the two poles of sexuality and mind have lead to self-destructive deformations of erotic self-organization which is the subject of Sigmund Freud's studies (Civilization and Its Discontents) as well as Herbert Marcuse's (Eros and Civilization). While Freud takes a pessimistic stance on whether these tensions can be dissolved, Marcuse argues against Freud that they are induced by social conditions, and that revolutionary change will be able to dissolve them. However, Marcuse's critique of Freud isn't fully consistent. An analysis of the inconsistencies suggests postulating a cognition instinct. Given this instinct, (revolutionary) change of social conditions could indeed dissolve the self-destructive tendencies obvious in current societies. Since self-destruction is "against nature's intention" (see above) and blocks its potential for self-organization, it can be said that this potential (nature's "erotic energy") is there to be ("intends") "liberated" ("unblocked from self-destruction"), and therefore nature, too, awaits the "revolution" (a social change that dissolves instincts of self-destruction).

Causality in the Social Sciences

Zum Problem der Kausalität in den Sozialwissenschaften (On the Problem of Causality in Social Sciences) Usually the concept of causality is discussed in the context of hard sciences, especially physics, which are considered to be paradigmatic. To transfer this concept of causality to social sciences is believed to be a merely pragmatic problem: since the objects of social sciences are highly complex and can hardly be isolated, social science is not as "hard" a science as physics, although on principle it could be. This essay argues for the other way round: that social sciences are paradigmatic for understanding the concept of causality: we couldn't understand the concept of causality in hard sciences had we never experienced it in our social world in the first place. David Hume had argued that when we refer to causality, all we really experience is that what we call the effect will always happen after what we call the cause. But how did we arrive at the idea of perceiving this as a causal relationship at all, one that points to an inner connection between cause and effect rather than the mere temporal sequence we perceive? The answer is that we get this idea from our social experiences. Social reality has the form of a text, i.e. everything in it has meaning and can and will be interpreted. Saying something is just as meaningful as not saying anything - both these actions deliver a message to the people around, whether intended or not. The rules that structure social reality are the rules of meaning respectively language; as speakers of our language we all know them implicitly. Therefore, to make our knowledge about them explicit, the social scientist has to only reconstruct them in their own medium - language respectively meaning. The rules exist objectively insofar as they actually generate the phenomena that need to be explained; they are generative rules. The hard scientist, however, applies the concept of causality only by analogy to her social experiences. She may assume the fact that the cause is always followed by the effect stems from the same inner connection we experience when we talk of reasons in the social world, but she'll never know. Since nature has no meaning and doesn't speak, there are no existing rules merely to be found and reconstructed (rules are a property of language). Instead, the hard scientist has to construct the rules. They don't exist objectively (language is no property of nature) but are used to subsume our discrete empiric data; as such they are subsuming rules. Therefore, it can be said that the hard scientist has to translate her object data into the medium of language and rules, while the social scientist need not do so. The act of translation moves hard sciences farther away from their objects, introducing new possibilities of error. In this respect, social sciences are less error-prone as hard sciences, contrary to common belief. However, due to their very nature of being subject to human free action (which constitutes change and thereby history), social rules are of less prognostic value than those in the hard sciences. Therefore, the question which kind of science comes closer to truth depends on the perspective. If the concept of truth is reduced to prognostic value (a prevalent view at least in Anglo-Saxon countries nowadays), it's certainly hard sciences. If it's not, it's probably social sciences. [
more (www.ritual.org)] END BLOCK QUOTE