AQUINAS, Philosophy of Saint Thomas.
St. Thomas Aquinas is both theologian and
philosopher, but in his thought the two disciplines are kept distinct even in
their closest alliance. Philosophy works to its conclusions by the unaided use
of human reason; theology depends upon divine revelation and the teaching
authority of the church. As a theologian he can make use of the methods and
findings of philosophy, and philosophy is thus ancillary to theology but still
distinct from it. The two sciences also differ in certain ways as to their
subject matter. Some truths can be known only from revelation and belong solely
to theology, for example, the mysteries of the Trinity and the Incarnation.
Some truths are proper to philosophy, e.g., the physical constitution of
bodies. A third class of truths belongs to both sciences. Thus the existence of
God can be known both by revelation and by the light of natural reason. In his
theory of knowledge Aquinas is realistic. There are no innate ideas; all our
knowledge takes its origin from sense experience. The higher Powers of the mind
are then able to act upon the sense data and to form abstract and universal
ideas. Aquinas' epistemology is thus in keeping with his psychology. Man is one
single complete substance, made up of material body and spiritual soul united
together. The soul is the substantial form, the animating and energizing
principle; it is the principle of life and therefore of growth, sensation,
thought, volition, and all other vital activities. Its highest powers are those
of intellect, which has the place of primacy, and of free will.
Metaphysics,
or first philosophy, is the science of being as being, and here again Aquinas
is a realist: he is concerned with the existent being of finite things, but
most of all with the supreme being in whom essence and existence are one and the same. He develops and applies
Aristotle's basic distinction between the actual or Perfect and the potential,
or what is capable of perfection. Infinite beings there is always found a
mixture of the potential with the actual. A child, for example, is an actual
child and is complete and perfect as a
child, but it has many potentialities that are as yet unfulfilled: it is
capable of being perfected in size, strength,
knowledge and the like. The only being that is devoid of all
mere potencies, and is completely actual, or absolutely perfect, is God, the
infinite being, pure actuality Connected with this doctrine of act and potency
are those of the four causes, material formal efficient, and final, and of matter and form in physical objects, both of which likewise derive from Aristotle.
God's existence is not self&-evident but
it can be proved by human reason in five ways.
These proofs are (1) from movement or change, the passage from the
potential to the actual (2) from cause and effect; (3) from the contingent and the necessary; (4)
from the grades of perfection found in things; and (5) from the order in the
universe. Aquinas states these arguments
very succinctly and concludes from them that there must be a first unmoved mover in whom there is no
mere potency or lack, a first cause a self-existent being, a supremely perfect
being and an adequate cause for the
order found in the universe. Each of these conclusions is a description of the
one supreme and infinite being, God, creator and conserves, first cause and
last end of all things. The human mind cannot fully comprehend God's nature,
but by means of analogy it can show that He must possess in a supreme degree
whatever true perfections are found in creatures Moreover, by "the way of
negation" it must exclude
from the concept of God every
attribute that implies defect. Hence it is known that God is omnipotent,
omniscient, all&-good, immutable and eternal. Since God is eternal, He
could have created the universe from eternity, Although human reason cannot
demonstrate that the world is not
eternal, that fact is known from revelation As to whether this is the best of
universes Aquinas makes careful distinctions. Relatively, that is, as a means
to God's purpose in creation, it is the best universe. In the absolute sense.
God could have had a different end in view and therefore could have made a
different and better universe. He gives a strong solution to the problem of
evil, both physical and moral and shows that
it is not incompatible with God's goodness and power.
In the
Summa Theologica and elsewhere Aquinas develops a complete moral system. He
analyzes the nature of the specifically human act, the act done under the control of reason and
will, and takes up the subject of
virtues and vices. The three theological virtues of faith hope, and charity, and their opposing vices and sins
are discussed, as are the Four cardinal
virtues, prudence, justice, fortitude, and temperance and the contrary vices. Not only are all the basic
ethical principles and problems
discussed but he is able to give a concrete solution to particular
problems, such as those of mendacity, homicide, theft, and many others. In his
treatment of morality Aquinas lays great stress on the concept of law, "a
dictate of practical reason, proceeding from the ruler who governs a perfect
community," and on the reality of the natural law, which is not different
from God's eternal law but a participation in it. Both in his moral treatiscs
and in doctrine on the state he advances principles that are essential to just
government and that have contributed to the growth of democracy. Thus he argues
for participation of all the people in the government, shows the necessity of a
wellordered society, emphasizes the advantages of a unified rule, and stresses
the evils of tyranny. Even
the physical sciences are not ignored, He suggests that the Ptolemaic
astronomic theory may be supplanted, and that the earth's roundness is provable
by both physics and mathematics.
Some of Aquinas' treatises are extended
discussions of the matter at hand, whereas in the Sunmia Theologica and certain
other works he brings to perfection the tripartite method of the medieval
schoolmen Aquinas' method consists of five parts, the first of which is the
statement of a problem, as "Whether custom can obtain the force of
law." Objections to the author's own position are then given followed by
an opinion or doctrine contrary to the objections. In the fourth part, which
constitutes the body of each article in the work, Aquinas' own doctrine is
stated, and at the end the original objections are answered, In the typical
article Aquinas will make use of both deductive and inductive reasoning,
appeals to experience and fact, and the authority of Sacred Scripture and
previous thinkers. He points out that in theology the argument from authority,
that is, Scripture and the pronouncements of the church, is the strongest
argument, but in philosophy the appeal to the opinion of other thinkers is the
weakest argument. His knowledge of the
literature of philosophy and theology is extraordinary. He makes
greatest use of the writings of Aristotle and St. Augustine, but countless
other men are quoted: great Greeks and Romans, such as Socrates, PIato, Plotinus,
Cicero and Seneca; the Fathers of the Church; Averroës, Avicenna, and other
Arabians; Jewish thinkers, like Mainionides and ibn-Gabirol; and earlier
medieval teachers. Yet he is always economical and never quotes without need.
He is never harsh or captious in criticism but follows the rule that truth is
to be respected rather than persons.
Great as Aquinas' analytical powers are, they
are surpassed by his powers of synthesis and construction. Making use of the
best that had been accomplished by the great patristic and earlier medieval
thankers, and of Aristotle's concepts, principles, and iiiethods, and adding
everywhere his own great original contributions, he produced new syntheses in
both philosophy and theology. He showed that there need not be, and indeed
could not be, genuine conflicts between faith and reason but that true theology
and sound science aid one another. His work illustrates both faith seeking
understanding and faith as a way to understanding. Its spirit likewise
illustrates the 'Amo ut intelligam of the mystics. He is always's the
intellectualist and the realist. Completeness, clearness, and exactness are his
marks as both thinker and writer
St. Thomas success was great in his own time
and has been long continued. From the 13th century on he has never lacked
followers although his influence waned between the 16th and the 19th centuries.
The revival of Thomistic studies has been of the most remarkable intellectual
movements since the mid-19th century, and today, the thought of St. Thomas
Aquinas is more widely held than ever before.