Site hosted by Angelfire.com: Build your free website today!

Cannons Essays,Reports, Termpapers

Home   Essays   Link    Contact Us

CannonEssays
Papers

EEMPIRICISM, is the philosophical doctrine that emphasizes the role of experience in human knowledge and minimizes the role of reason. The term "empiricism" is derived from the Greek word empiria, meaning trail or experience. Empiricism as a doctrine is opposed to rationalism. To understand the doctrine, it is important to distinguish two central theories that are characteristic of empirical philosophies: a theory of meaning and a theory of knowledge.

                                                           Theory of Meaning

The empiricist theory of meaning has traditionally been stated as a theory about the genesis of our ideas or concepts. In the Middle Ages it was summarized in the  formula Nihil est in intellectu qued non prius fuerit in sensu ("Nothing is in the intellect that has not been previously in sensation"). This was essentially the thesis of John Locke's epoch-making polemic. An essay Concerning Human Understanding (1960), against the rationist doctrine of innate ideas. The mind at birth, Locke maintained, is like a blank sheet of paper, or tabula nasa, and every idea that it acquires must come from experience-either from vision, hearing, taste, toch, and other sense experiences or from observing the operations of our own minds by means of what Locke called "inner sense."

Daivd Hume, who restated this restated this theory about the genesis of ideas in the opening paragraphs of his Treatise of Human Nature (1739), gave it greater strength and precision by drawing a distinction between ideas and impressions. All our ideas, he said, come from impressions, and impressions are defined to include sensations, passions, and emotions, as they occur in their original vividness.

The contrasting rationalist to which Locke and Hume were opposed is clearly stated in the writings of Rene Desecrates and other 17th century rationalists. Desecrates distinguished two functions of human reason: a discursive function that enables us to draw conclusions from premises, and an intuitive function that enables us to grasp certain ultimate truths and concepts directly. Although many of our ideas are acquired through sense experience, there are some -notably the idea of the soul and the idea of material substance-that must be acquire a priori (that is, independently of experience) by means of rational intuition.

In the 20th century, empiricists have tended to formulate their theory of meaning not by reference to the genesis of our concepts, but by reference to the experiences that determine whether a concept has been applied correctly. One outstanding example of this change of emphasis is the pragmatic theory of meaning, which was originally formulated by Charles Sanders Peircee in the naxim: "Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearings you conceive the object of your conception to have. Then, your conception of these effects is the whole of your conception of the object."

The verifiability theory of meaning, which is closely associated with the philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein and the school of logical positivism, represents a very similar position. However an empiricist theory of meaning is formulated, there are certain basic terms that are usually excluded as meaningless unless interpreted in a purely empirical way. Thus for the typical empiricist the soul can be conceived only as a stream of conscious experiences, matter only as a pattern of sensible qualities, and necessary casual connection only as uniform sequences of events.

                                                             Theory of Knowledge.

Whatever the source of our concepts, a further question arises concerning the source of human knowledge and the justification of our beliefs. Rationalists have traditionally maintained that there are some general truths such as "Every event has a cause," the elementary propositions of mathematics, and sometimes the basic principles of ethics, which are self-evident and known a priori by means of rational intuition. Empiricists have denied that we have such a faculty of rational intuition. They have usually conceded, however, that the truths of mathematics are indeed a priori and thus to be sharply distinguished from the truths of physics, biology, psychology, and other natural  sciences. In the natural sciences our knowledge is obtained a posteriori by means of experimentation, observation, and induction, whereas this experimental method has no place in the solution of problems of pure mathematics.

To account for this distinction the empiricist usually maintains that the truths of mathematics are merely propositions that express the relations of meaning that hold among our concepts. Thus "2 t- 2 = 4" is true simply because of the way "2," "plus," "equals," and "4" are defined, and the theorems of geometry are true simply because of the way such terms as "line," "point," and "between" are defined. In other words, all such mathematical propositions have the same epistemic status as the statement "Every wife has a husband," which is true because a wife is defined as a woman who has a husband. They are all, in a broad sense of the word, tautologies. Hume stated this empiricist theory of mathematics by distinguishing between "relations of ideas" and "matters of fact": the propositions of mathematics merely express the relations among our ideas or

concepts, whereas all knowledge about matters of fact (that is, about the actual world) must be derived from experience.

Immanuel Kant's use of the terms "analytic"  and "synthetic" has enabled subsequent philosophers to state the issue even more precisely. A judgment is analytic, as Kant uses the word, if it can be shown to be true merely by analysis of the concepts in it. A judgment is synthetic, on the contrary, if its predicate really adds something new to the subject. Using these terms, therefore, we may define an empiricist as one

who believes that all rational (a priori truths are analytic. Kant's own Critique of Pure Reason (1781; revised 1787) is a defense of the rationalistic thesis that - there are some synthetic a priori truths. However, Kant denies that these truths extend beyond the range of possible human experience.

After 1940, certain philosophers, notably Willard Van Orman Quine and Morton Gabriel White in the United States, challenged the validity of the distinction between the analytic and the synthetic. They suggested the possibility of an empiricism even more thoroughgoing than that of Hume-an empiricism that would deny a priori knowledge altogether.