EPISTEMOLOGY
Epistemology
studies the nature, sources, limitations, and validity of knowledge. The
questions it asks itself are, How do we know, and how certain can we be of it?
There
are two main sources of knowledge: reason and experience. Although both sources
would seem to be intimately involved in knowledge, historically the question
has tended to divide philosophers into two camps: those who placed their stress
on reason and those who placed it on experience.
Philosophers
who chose reason as our only trustworthy source of knowledge came to be called
rationalists. These thinkers-Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz-shared a number of
characteristics: they all lived in Europe; all believed that reason by itself
is capable of arriving at a true knowledge of reality; all believed in the doctrine
of innate ideas; their model of the perfect science was mathematics; and their
test of whether our ideas are true or not is intuition: "the absence of
doubt in the unclouded and attentive mind."
Philosophers
who chose experience as our prime source of knowledge came to be called
empiricists. These thinkers-Locke, Berkeley, and Hume-also shared a number of
characteristics in common: they all lived in Britain; all put their faith in
experience as our main source of knowledge, doubting whether human reason is
capable by itself of arriving at anything more than a few basic propositions
about reality: all believed that the mind at birth is a tabula rasa, utterly
blank of ideas; and their test of truth was external, not internal: Ideas are
true if they correspond with what we can find in the outside world.
Each school, by proceeding on its
assumptions, arrived at a dead end. Rationalism professed absolute confidence
in reason's ability to arrive at a perfect knowledge of reality, yet the
results each rationalist achieved differed markedly from those achieved by the
others. Descartes's reasoning led him to dualism, Spinoza's to monism, and
Leibniz's to pluralism. Empiricism prided itself on its attachment to
experimental science, yet in the end none of the major empiricists was able to
give an intelligible account of some of the basic concepts underlying science
itself. Locke had to admit that substance was "a something, I know not
what"; Berkeley said that if we do not have an "idea" of the
self we nevertheless have a "notion" of it; and Hume said that what
we call causes are only a series of "loose" or "separate"
events.
lmmanuel
Kant tried to rescue what was valuable in these two schools of thought by means
of a new attack on the problem of knowledge. He came to realize that each
school had arrived at an impasse because of a wrong assumption about the mind's
relation to the world. If we are to understand how knowledge is possible, we
must come to see, Kant argued, that the mind is not, as both rationalism and
empiricism assumed, totally independent of the world of objects it tries to
know but rather contributes something to that world. Kant tried to identify
this contribution in the Critique.
The
Critique is divided into three main parts: the Transcendental Aesthetic, the
Transcendental Analytic, and the Transcendental Dialectic. The first deals with
the faculty of sensibility and shows how synthetic a priori propositions are
possible in Transcendental Analytic, and the Transcendental Dialectic. The
first deals with the faculty of sensibility and shows how synthetic a priori
propositions are possible in mathematics The second deals with the faculty of
understanding and shows how synthetic a priori propositions are possible in
natural science. The third deals with the faculty of reason and shows how and
why the a priori elements offered by it and the claims made on their behalf by
traditional metaphysics are not possible.
Although
Kant's contribution to our understanding of these matters was profound much
still remains unsettled and in doubt. As a result of these philosophic labors
however we now see more clearly that the source of an idea cannot guarantee its
validity (as rationalism had mistakenly believed); that the importance of
empirical evidence lies not so much in being the source of ideas (as empiricism
also mistakenly thought) as in being a means of testing and confirming them;
that the process of information gathering, in order to be fruitful, must be
guided (and Kant was right about this) by leading questions or hypotheses; but
(and here is where he was probably mistaken) that the dream of an absolutely
certain science built of synthetic a priori propositions is impossible.