IT BEGAN HERE
Philosophy
and science arose in the sixth century B.C. in the ancient Greek city of
Miletus in Asia Minor. It was the wonder and curiosity of the Greeks about this
world, rather than concern about the next, that led to the rise of philosophy
and science. Discovering the world for the first time not only led these first
thinkers to raise new questions about it but also led them to pursue these new
questions in a new way. They sought natural rather than supernatural knowledge
about the world, and their goal was the achievement of a system of unified
knowledge rather than a collection of facts.
The
first philosophers and scientists did not succeed in seeing the world entirely
anew. There were a number of beliefs (concerning the genesis, government, and
composition of the world) that they inherited from the past, which continued to
influence their thinking on the new questions they raised.
The first philosopher and scientist
was Thales, who flourished around 585 B.C. The first question raised by Thales
and his successors concerned the nature of "Being." The great variety
and profusion of things surrounding us must all have arisen, Thales and his
successors speculated, from some one fundamental substance. Picking one of the
four elements mentioned by tradition, Thales said that it must all have come
from water. Anaximander, believing that it would have been unjust (and a threat
to the harmony of the cosmos) for one of the elements to be elevated above the
others, speculated that it could not have been any one of the four but
something more primitive and prior to them. He identified it as the
Boundless-some neutral,
indeterminate, and infinite stuff. Anaximenes, the
last member of this school, trying to preserve and synthesize what seemed best
in the thought of his two predecessors, suggested that the fundamental stuff
was air-a substance not quite so definite as water and not so indefinite and
empty as Anaximander's Boundless. The other three elements, he further
suggested, arose from it by way of the principle of condensation and
rarefaction.
Thinkers
soon realized that the first question raised and discussed: "What is the
nature of that stuff which seems constantly to be changing or becoming
something else? " entailed another, even more fundamental question:
"What is change itself?" and they turned their attention to it.
The
First to do so was Parmenides, who argued that change or becoming, if we use
reason as our guide and are not deceived by what our senses tell us, must be an
illusion. Since space, logically, is nothing, and since nothing is not, it does
not exist. If there is no space, there cannot be motion in which it can take
place, and without motion there cannot be change. Furthermore, since for many
things to exist there must be space between them, and since there is no space,
all there can be is just one thing. Parmenides called that unitary, unchanging
being the It.
Parmenides's
subtle and abstract arguments were strongly reinforced by one of his followers,
Zeno the Eleatic, in the form of certain paradoxes that continue to baffle
thinkers to this day.
Heraclitus,
a thinker living at about the same time as Parmenides, adopted a diametrically
opposite view. Far from change being unreal, it is the most real thing there
is. "Everything flows-nothing abides," he said. Concerning the nature
of that which is in constant flux, he said it was fire.
The
effort on the part of subsequent thinkers to preserve what was correct in each
extreme finally resulted in the theory of atomism, a theory that proved to be
an ingenious solution not only to the problem of Becoming but also to the
problem of Being. The atomists suggested that the basic stuff out of which
everything arises is atoms-tiny, indestructible particles, infinite in number.
Bodies, large and small, are collections of atoms and arise and disappear as a
result of the generation or dissolution of atoms. Parmenides was correct in
maintaining that the real is unchanging, for the real consists of atoms and they
do not change; and Heraclitus was correct in insisting on change, for change,
too, is real but only happens to complexes of atoms. And the Milesians were
correct in seeking a unitary source of Being. Atoms are that source.
Although
it is remarkable that thinkers living in the fifth century B.C. should succeed
in arriving at a physical theory that in its essentials is still accepted by
science today, what is even more noteworthy about both them and their
predecessors was the new spirit that guided their investigations. In them, for
the first time, supernaturalism gave way to naturalism, making possible the
birth of science and philosophy.