Site hosted by Angelfire.com: Build your free website today!

 

Introduction to

Critical Theory

The Empirical and the Transcendental

 

*  The Difference Between the Empirical and the Transcendental   

 

It is inevitable that we pass through some implicit or explicit theoretical understanding or interpretation when participating in critical discourse.   Sometimes this understanding or interpretation is a matter of convention, usage, expectation or otherwise anticipating structure.  At other times this understanding or interpretation is rooted more specifically in traditional theoretical discourse.  Whatever the case, there is nothing we come to without, from the beginning, adding something extra to the bare fact of our experience.  For this reason the notion of the bare fact, without anything added, is impossible.  If it were possible it would be called the empirical.  Empirical experience concerns the experience of the here and now—our experience of presently existing things like these chairs and tables and these other people.  Empirical experience puts us in a place and a time that we feel exist independently of our experience of it.  So it is the kind of experience that we ought to be able to be confident about.  However, as the history of philosophy shows, no one has ever been able to isolate the empirical in a way that could be considered truly objective.  The closest we have come to this ideal is through modern science, whose methods of judgment and testing (empiricism) demand that our theories be made explicit and explicitly testable according to the palpable existence of the things in question (rocks for the geologist, for instance).  However these methods are always based upon certain clearly defined axioms and postulates, which rest upon certain less well defined or understood assumptions and interpretations.  Opposed to the empirical is the transcendental.  The transcendental refers to any form or pattern of being or thinking which stands outside and exists independently of the empirical.  Mathematics is the best example but as the influential philosopher Martin Heidegger pointed out, the mathematical simply means that which is “already known.”  In “The Age of the World Picture,” he writes: “Ta mathematica means for the Greeks that which man knows in his observation of whatever is and in his intercourse with things: the corporeality of bodies, the vegetable character of plants, the animality of animals, the humanness of man.  Alongside these, belonging also to that which is already known, i.e., to the mathematical, are numbers. [...] Only because numbers represent, as it were, the most striking of always-already-knowns, and thus offer the most familiar instance of the mathematical, is "mathematical" promptly reserved as a name for the numerical” (118-119).  It seems that there is no knowledge as such that does not pass through something “always already known.”  The relationship between experience and the always already known falls into the traditional and pervasive distinction between the empirical and the transcendental.  Modern critical theory gets going by finding problems with this distinction.  There are some things, apparently, which cannot be reduced to this difference (like difference itself, as we shall discover).  The literary text (and by extension whatever it is we mean by textuality) is particularly resistant to the kinds of thinking based upon this distinction.  To get to the empirical one has to pass through perception—in its crudest form, through the senses—and to get to the transcendental one must pass through the intelligible (understanding and then to reason itself, ratiocination, logic and the lofty mathematical and then on, it is supposed, to the spiritual realm, which is, of course, fundamentally opposed to the crude material one).  But one never achieves either the empirical or the transcendental in any pure way.  Instead, it seems, human experience is stuck somewhere between.  This somewhere between is defined and delimited by the standard notion of a text.         

 

*  Experience and Theory

Theory: an explanation or system of anything: an exposition of the abstract principles of a science or art: speculation as opposed to practice. [Gr. Theorema, -atos, spectacle, speculation, theorem, theoria, view, theory--theoreein, to be a spectator, to view.]

Science: knowledge: knowledge ascertained by observation and experiment, critically tested, systematised and brought under general principles: a department or branch of such knowledge or study.  [L. Scienta--sciens, -entis, pr.p. of scire, to know.]

Theory, especially in its modern form as science, has always been opposed to experience.  I intend to substantially weaken that opposition.  Consider the following description of a football match between Queens Park Rangers, playing at home, and West Ham, the visiting team:

During the first half the Hammers probed down the left flank.  Revelling in the space, the speed of Sylvester Drayon was always going to pose problems for the home side’s number two.  With scant minutes remaining before the half-time whistle, the black winger cut in on the left back and delivered a searching cross, converted by Lee Fredge, the East London striker, with inch-perfect precision.  After the interval Rangers’ fortunes revived as they exploited their superiority in the air.  Bobby Bondavitch’s men offered stout resistance and the question remained: could the blues translate the pressure they were exerting into goals?  In the seventy-fourth minute Keith Spare produced a pass that split the visitors’ defence, and Dustin Housely rammed the equalizer home.  A draw looked the most likely result until a disputed penalty decision broke the deadlock five minutes from the final whistle.  Keith spare made no mistake from the spot.  Thus the Shepherd’s Bush team ran out surprise 2-1 winners.

How, if at all, does the description make the match itself accessible to you?  Do you have to know the rules and conventions of football to understand what is going on?  Do you have to be familiar with the conventions of sports reporting in the press or on television?  Would it be possible to produce another account of this match (which we will presume we have never seen) on the basis of this description?  We could say: “Queens Park Rangers won 2-1.  Lee Fedge scored the first goal for West Ham in the first half.  Keith Spare scored the equalizer for Queens Park Rangers in the second.  Just before the end a penalty in favour of Queens Park Rangers allowed Spare to score the winning goal.”  Abstracting fewer details, what we might think of as the most significant ones, we nonetheless repeat the same pattern although we change the order a bit, revealing the result at the start and then giving an account of the match.  What the quotation represents is a version of a specific and recognisable art (implying no value judgment by this).  There are certain rules that this very specific way of describing a football match adheres to.  You don’t for instance use the same phrase twice to describe a team.  So West Ham are “the Hammers, East London, and the visitors” while Shepherd Bush are “the home side, Rangers, Bobby Bondavitch’s men, the blues and the Shepherds Bush team.”  If you study the quotation you may find evidence to suggest that the account, whilst apparently objective, is given from the point of view of a supporter of the winning team.  You have probably identified the style of the account as belonging to the sporting media, a newspaper possibly, or a television or radio commentary.  It is a conventional way of seeing a football match.  Imagine an account by someone who knows nothing of the game and has just watched this one for the first time.  Then imagine an account by someone who does know about football but who doesn’t read the papers or watch it on television.  Each time the account would be quite different.  So much depends upon knowledge that is often taken for granted.  This particular example gives us an extremely stylised way of describing things.  To an extent, for those of us who did not see this match, it is a cipher that allows us to see it.  The description itself is a way of seeing.

I have used this example for three reasons.  First, this very specific structure or pattern of seeing should help to emphasise that all descriptions of things that occur follow patterns and rules, however loosely.  Secondly, the example of a football match gives us an event that is itself a repeatable rule-governed activity.  It has two teams of eleven players each. The match is limited by strict duration divided into two halves.  Strict rules govern the scoring of points and a referee with a team of linesmen arbitrate.  It is a strictly structured event with an unpredictable outcome.  Thirdly, as you will have guessed if you didn’t already know, if only because of the silly names of the players,  the account is a fiction, a rather obvious parody of a rather crude style.  Let the account as you read it represent “theory” in a basic form.  It is a structured, rule governed, style of seeing something.  Let the match itself stand for experience.  It is something that happens and can be witnessed; it is an event  governed by rules, conventions and expectations but undecided until it is over.  The parody, which allows us to “see” an event that never took place, suggests that theory, in its basic possibility, is neither constrained by experience nor governed by science.  Experience is structured.  Theory is structured.  The following sections will give an account of how this structuring occurs.  

 

*  Object, Concept, aim: what theory is and why it is necessary

The most basic problem for theory is the need to formulate concepts that can stand over against objects, as traditional science does.  A scientific theory might, for instance, provide an explanation, a system and a set of principles which would explain, describe and predict processes in the natural world.  In the arts and social sciences, however, theories need to be formulated that can explain, describe and predict processes involving persons, events and historical situations.  Traditionally this need has been met in diverse ways by separate disciplines, like sociology, psychology, anthropology, history, in the social sciences; and music, literary studies, art history, and linguistics in the arts.  Since their respective developments during the 18th and 19th centuries, and until recently, these disciplines have been more or less content to pursue their own individual paths towards the aim of scientific objectivity in an academic atmosphere of mutual distance and respect.  Yet even within any one of these diverse disciplines controversial debates constantly arise and are seldom resolved to the satisfaction of a consensus.  In other words the integrity of all autonomous academic disciplines in the arts and social sciences has always been on the verge of crisis.

Over the last quarter of the 20th century theoretical issues have played an increasingly significant role for such disciplines, reflected in the fact that “theory” has come to define specific and often central strands for most kinds of course.  Not only does “theory” now seem to describe a field within which new disciplines like Critical Theory, Cultural Studies, Film Theory, Literary Theory, Social Theory, Feminism Postcolonial Theory, Media Studies, etc., all in many senses meet.  But it also describes a development within which, to a large extent, otherwise diverse disciplines have begun to interact.

However the recent history of theoretical developments has not been one of organic growth, mutual tolerance and support.  Theories abound that contest and explain each other, each from their own particular points of view or chosen grounds.  Herein lies a paradox.  If theory develops through contestation and debate, each perspective contesting others while making specific claims to objectivity or truth, then what or who can ultimately provide sound objective principles for academic work in these disciplines?  Even to say that there are no such principles is to implicitly lay down such a ground, and that too requires theoretical explanation.

The answer to this problem lies with the root of theory itself.  The very word carries residual historical associations that we need to understand as having been transformed by the more influential recent work.  It will be useful to discuss this transformation here because it embodies the process or pattern by which traditional modes of thinking generally have undergone transformations in contemporary theory.  Our aim is, on one hand, to reveal how contemporary theory develops through the constant transformation of both traditional and common sense ways of thinking and, on the other hand, to show that the possibilities for this kind of transformation have been implicit in philosophical and theoretical texts throughout western history.

We must first return to the common and traditional senses of the word “theory” itself.  What does it mean traditionally, and what does it mean in everyday language?  Traditionally, a science or an art can be thought of as the application of certain principles that may be abstracted in explanation, exposition, or as a system.  So a theory is an explanation or a system of anything, an exposition of the abstract principles of a science or an art.  Theory is the speculative, abstract aspect in contrast to the actual practice of that science or art.  A poet would make use of what is called “prosody” as a theory of poetry, including rules for rhyming, metre, assonance, dissonance, etc.  The actual practice in this case, and this will be instructive, may well involve creatively breaking some of those rules.  In science, just think of Isaac Newton’s theory of gravity or Albert Einstein’s theory of relativity (E=MC2), both abstract systems that account for all known possibilities in their field (the movement of bodies in space).  Sigmund Freud’s theory of repression and the unconscious, as well as Darwin’s theory of evolution follow this pattern, but with some subtle differences.  For now we note merely that traditionally theory is coupled either with a practice (for which it supplies a set of rules), or with a situation (for which it supplies an explanation).  In any given discipline theory in fact usually plays both these roles.  Theory always involves either working with methods that provide the means to formulate explanations, or working with explanations that provide the means to understand objects.  It is unlikely that any discipline could do without some sort of theory.

If we now investigate the conventional concept of theory further we find that it is in fact a modification of a wider ranging concept.  This modification has occurred through long term historical trends and across languages.  We need to return to the language of the ancient Greeks to see how and why this modification, which has many parallels, has taken place.  We do this not to find the “real” meaning of the word theory–the real meaning of a word is not simply what it used to mean–but it can help to show the kind of trends in thought that occur over long stretches of history.  In ancient Greek theoria means “way of seeing” or “setting in view”; and this root provides not only our own current sense of the word theory but also the notion of the theatre, the place where dramas or events (like plays or operations) can be viewed; theory indicates the role of an audience too.  The root, at base, involves the sense of seeing, and this sense is precisely what is carried over into the meaning of the word theory.  Theory is fundamentally a way of seeing things or of setting things in view.  When someone begins a sentence with the phrase “in my view ...” we may expect, however humble, contradictory or crude, at least the trace of a theory.  (“In my view the Communist Party would do a better job than the PAP” indicates at least a basic political theory; “Friends is funnier than Under One Roof” suggests the vestiges of a theory of comedy.)  So in the broadest sense we each use theory all the time, or at least while we are awake, certainly while we think, speak or write, for it is in thinking, speaking and writing that theory is unavoidably expressed. 

So the conventional meaning of the word theory can be seen as a  modification of a more general meaning, a modification designed perhaps to avoid the pitfalls of everyday language with its imprecision and lack of systematic foundation.  Here, however, we face a paradox.  For we begin to see that no theory, however systematic one tries to make it, can escape its own foundations in the shifting, often quite vague sphere of everyday understanding and common sense.  Theory in the sciences and arts is each time a powerful modification of everyday understanding, infected with a common sense and informed by a historical background. 

Now this is only rarely a problem for the various well founded arts or scientific disciplines.  Each discipline is informed by a tradition of customs and practices supported by theories and methodologies that are ideally suited for their purpose.  If, for instance, theories of human motivation help managers manipulate the behaviour of their workforce so that it is more efficient and productive, so much the better if the theories are in tune with the common sense thinking of most managers.  But every now and then a crisis occurs where basic assumptions and principles may need questioning and perhaps setting up afresh. Contributions to the development of a given discipline are generally made within existing rules and any changes are painlessly gradual.  Without rules one could hardly function at all, so one puts up with nagging problems with the odd basic principle.  But a crisis in any given discipline involves a reexamination of first principles and basic grounds.  A striking and famous historical example would be the so called Copernican revolution in which it was discovered, to the shock of the scientific world, that the planets circled in orbit around the sun rather than around the earth.  Not only was this discovery “counter-intuitive” in that it went against the common sense but it went against the most entrenched teaching of the church whose authority at the time was of course all powerful.  In this case a theoretical discovery not only contradicted the rules but actually broke the law.  The kind of “decentring” that occurred over the following hundred years or so is typical of the adjustments that need to be made during a crisis.  Now try to imagine a discipline that is constantly in crisis, continually questioning its own basic premises.  Critical theory often seems to be in this state: continually in crisis, without faith in any founding frame of theoretical reference, constantly questioning its own or others’ basic principles.  But this is only the way it seems.  Critical theory only seems to be in crisis because of its basic field of analysis, which is the rhetorical, historical and cultural background from which all theories must have at some time emerged.  It is this background of intimate, residually historical, culturally focused ideas, feelings and opinions that make up a confused yet apparently coherent everyday understanding that contemporary theory turns its attention to. Theory, in other words, is turned around and applied to its own grounds in both traditional and everyday understanding.  Thus we tend to find a more or less consistently applied self-reflexivity accompanying most influential forms of critical theory, because in the first place the only concepts available are those we use in traditional and everyday practice.

So we should now be able to see the difference, on one hand, between traditional and conventional concepts of theory and new meanings of the term, on the other.  The new sense involves a practice which concerns itself with the very grounds of theory generally, the limits of any theory.  So, you might ask, why do we still call it theory?  But what else could we call it?  We are from the beginning limited to what we can say by concepts derived from the evolutionary patterns of rhetoric, so we must use the terms available, even if it means extending and transforming them as we have with “theory.”  And that is the basic method of contemporary theory.  As we look back over the history of the term we find that there has always been this tension between a “theoretical” (systematic, abstract) point of view and a “pre-theoretical” (everyday, common sense) one.  By investigating the nature of the so called pre-theoretical background, contemporary theory radicalises the very notion of theory itself, undoing the grounded certainty of traditional theoretical positions.  In other words, today we find the same patterns at work in both theoretical and pre-theoretical domains of thought, a tension that describes the intractable mutual relationship between the two. 

 

*  Object and Concept

Traditionally, all objects that are set-into-view by a science are set down under “concepts.”  A concept is a “general notion,” a notion that can account for a range of examples.  Thus theory is nothing without concepts.  The concepts of a theory are designed to account for the range of objects that fall under its domain.  In the “natural” or “physical” sciences, for instance,  we find that a concept like oscillation can account for a range of motions: the vibrations of a stringed instrument when struck or bowed, the swinging of a pendulum, the movement of a needle on a lie detector, the body’s shivering when exposed to cold.  The concept oscillation accounts for an abstract relationship between each of these motions and thus pays no attention to the particular, idiosyncratic aspects of our examples of it.  Thus oscillation is simply “swinging to and fro; vibration” and we need make no reference to the cello, violin or guitar, no reference to the lie detector and no reference to a body. 

We should also be able to see that each of these examples falls under a single concept by analogy.  There can be few more decisive concepts in theory than analogy, for analogy is the very concept that describes the process of making concepts.  Think about the ways in which the concept of oscillation gets used to describe–by analogy–types of text, like theoretical texts, as well as fictional and mass media texts.  A critic may say that the arguments of Walter Benjamin oscillate between the historical and the mystical; or one might argue that the narrative in George Eliot’s Daniel Deronda oscillates uneasily between her two plot lines, or that the popular British TV series Crocodile Shoes oscillates between representations of the North and the South of England, as well as between England and the USA.  In each case the term oscillation presupposes that the textual elements referred to can be separated out into contrasting poles, differences which can be represented through the analogy of oscillation as opposites or contrasts. 

All the concepts in theoretical arguments have their basis in the use of analogy, which is a means of abstracting typical trends, patterns and processes in concepts that can be regarded as general.  By the same account critical theory develops often by pointing out the sometimes inappropriate uses of analogical concepts and by developing new ones more appropriate to the situation under study.  That is to say that one cannot use any concept in contemporary theory uncritically.  One must be aware of the history of its development as a concept, of the specific uses to which it has been put, of the ways in which it has become currency in theoretical discourse.  Many thinkers will go to great pains in defining terms precisely as their argument develops, and this is very important as it helps readers get a firm sense of what is being argued.  However, given what I have said about the relation between theoretical discourse and everyday discourse, we should be aware that no precise definition will be able to neutralise or pacify the clamour of historical, cultural and everyday discourses that necessarily inhabit and infect the theoretical term that is fundamentally parasitic upon them.  Thus there is no real alternative to the consistently self-critical, or self-reflexive use of theoretical terminology that characterises so many of the most influential thinkers.  You will doubtless find that much theoretical writing today fails to consider this important point and this results in apparently jargon-laden texts which reflect the fashion of the moment for certain concepts that have achieved academic currency (and which often filter into use in the popular media). 

Notice my own use of analogy here, the analogy of currency, likening the use of current coinage in a relatively closed economy to the use of language in relatively closed institutional contexts.  The concept of economy is, as we shall see, very important and has wide ranging uses in contemporary theory.  What it disallows in theoretical language is the use of any term that can stand alone, outside or beyond the system that gives it currency.  In other words all concepts have an integral relation not simply to others in a relatively closed system, but to all other concepts in a language, as well as to a range of sometimes quite difficult choices with regard to translation.  The concept of oscillation, for instance, might indicate frequency or periodicity, concepts associated with regularity and recurrence; but it also might, rather differently, indicate changeableness, under which term it shares similarities with fitfulness, transience and agitation.  Oscillation is also understood in relation to concepts regarded as opposite to it, like disorder and discontinuity (if oscillation is thought of as periodisation), or stability, permanence and fixture (if it is considered as “chopping and changing”), which reveals that the single concept “oscillation” is capable, depending on context, of meanings that are potentially opposite to each other and therefore mutually exclusive.  In principle this capability is a feature of all language. 

When the need to translate a concept arises, quite precise attention to the context is necessary, as well as a knowledge of current uses in the language it is being translated into.  Oscillate in the German might be oszillieren or schwingen if the context is physical; or it could be schwanken for the lie detector as well as for a great many of the analogical meanings that we have used where oszillieren would sound odd in the German.  The concept of “translation” too works to an extent in analogy with the concept of “currency,” as coinage can be translated (“changed”) by virtue of a “rate of exchange” into any other currency.  The same is true, of course, for any word, although precise translations are impossible because one cannot at the same time translate the whole system to which the one word belongs.  Such a system is by no means fixed and unchangeable but undergoes a continuous process of transformation.  As I will show throughout this book, theory must operate very much on the boundaries of fixity and change in critical thought, and is consistently concerned with the family of concepts concerning translation, analogy, and exchange.

Having complicated the notion of “concept,” I will now discuss the ways in which the concepts of critical theory relate to their special objects.  First, what is the object or what are the objects of theory?  Before we can answer that question we must ask, what is an object?  As with all important concepts used in theory, it is necessary to explore the constructions, histories and conventional uses of the concept “object,” in order to tease out the deeper implications of its use.  In the physical world, it would seem, there is no difficulty in establishing what objects are.  An object is simply a thing presented or capable of being presented to the senses.  What this means is that an object is something that can be observed.  If we begin with the least problematical examples we can easily see what is involved.  The most basic kind of object that can be observed is a material thing, something in the world like a rock, a tree, a dog or cat, a man, a woman, a child.  Leaving aside for the moment (although we will come back to this directly) the fact that rocks and people are conventionally considered to be objects with very different qualities, their shared status as objects in the most basic sense remains the same.  That is, each thing can be regarded as existing outside and as being independent of the mind observing it.  This indicates already that the concept “object” has its most basic sense in relation to a correlative concept, that of the “subject” who does the observing, who is in possession of “a mind” and is thus capable of understanding the concepts (like rock, tree, dog, cat, man, woman, child) which stand over against the objects in the world (the things to which those concepts are said to refer).  Now, because the concept of “subject” is supposed to refer to the very being that does the observing, it is not surprising that it is one of the most difficult and important concepts in the history of theory.  The subject is the one who sees and who sets things into view.

An object is, therefore, not simply some discrete thing standing passively around in the world but something in the world that has been set into view in some more or less specific way by the subject who observes it, or at least by subjects who habitually observe things in specific ways.  In other words, rocks, trees and people share the same status as objects but are viewed in very different ways by different people, i.e. as having different qualities.  An object is something upon which attention, interest or some emotion is fixed.  A botanist will see an oak tree in a very different light–will “set it into view” in a different way–to the way a painter or a person walking in the country or a lumberjack or timber-merchant would.  It is possible to say that each of these different people have different interests in the tree, and thus see it as a different object when their respective attentions are fixed upon it.  In the case of people, things get very complex.  A child might be the object of a parent’s love or irritation, siblings may be the objects of each others’ envy; a stranger may be the object of someone’s secret desire.  In principle the situation remains when rather than an individual a whole group is taken as an object.  An identification of “racial type” or a gender is a way of objectifying a group, possibly as being “other” or “different.”  These concepts can then be (and often are) applied to individuals in a way which also reflects the attitudes of the subjects who have set their objects into view in this way.  There are also concepts, like virtue and crime, that seem not to refer to any object that is in any basic sense “in-the-world.”  This reveals all the more that concepts denote objects in an active, productive way, creating their objects, rather than simply reflecting or representing them.

People collectively are actually the objects of disciplines like anthropology, sociology and psychology, in which case concepts like “behaviour,” “group dynamics,” “personality” or “attitude” govern the ways in which people are set into view.  And because those disciplines aim for scientific status, they must find legitimate criteria for objectivity, to help reduce the tendency for subjective interests to inform observation.  So means are found for making generalisations.  People can then be understood objectively thanks to empirical methods like the statistical analysis of measurable segments of society.  But the scientific viewpoint is itself a “point-of-view,” or more specifically, a particular way of setting objects into view.  And the “subject” of a scientific viewpoint is no less subjective for being scientific.  This is not to suggest that contemporary theory should abandon science, but rather it is to suggest that the scientific viewpoint is, in contemporary theory, made more self-critical in its awareness of the styles by which different disciplines (both theoretical and practical) set their objects into view.  There is no pure objectivity.  Traditionally objectivity would be a condition under which objects could be described and/or acted upon that was not coloured by sensations or emotions.  In a more significant formulation it would also be a condition under which objects could be described and/or acted upon uncoloured by any way or style of setting things into view at all.  But there is no way of setting things in view that is not coloured by a way or style of doing so.  There can be no pure objectivity because the attitude of the subject always intrudes and intervenes in an active way.  Take the example of science.  We have got so used to adopting a technological way of speaking in the modern world, especially where academic disciplines are concerned, that we often fail to see that technological ways of speaking themselves constitute a positive style.  In other words, while such ways of speaking attain to a condition of transparent description and, ultimately, to objective truth, they are in fact part of a system, a set of tendencies, habits of thought and conventional laws of operation. 

In order to attain to the level of scientific objectivity one must first learn all the rules and terminology that characterise the science in question.  Once that has been done one needs to deny or at least ignore the fact that this privileged viewpoint is no less a subjective setting-into-view than the random and confused thoughts of an “unlearned” person who must rely on myths and hearsay.  As I have suggested already, neither the blindly technological nor the naively conventional ways of setting things into view is really desirable if we are genuinely concerned with these questions (interested in, affected by and even fixated on them).  But in contemporary theory the technological way of thinking and writing is subtly altered in accordance with the following realisation: as a style, as a specifically historical and cultural way of setting things into view, the technological way of thinking is potentially the best one available to us (not least because it is so powerful), so long as we are sufficiently aware of its own situation as a particular and not necessarily more objective viewpoint amongst others, with which it shares a more general, historical and cultural background.   That background can be made more visible.

So the concepts that are developed in contemporary theory are designed to allow us access to elusive objects.  But these “objects” are very often the creation of the system which gives their concepts currency.  And their use often implies a breakdown in any hard and fast distinction between subjects and objects.  The concept for this chapter is “theory” itself, and I have demonstrated the way in which a theoretical point of view can proceed by questioning the very grounds of the theoretical point of view itself, which is simply one specific way of setting objects into view.  We can use the analogy of framing and say that theory frames its objects in specific ways.  You can take this to mean both in the way pictures are framed to provide tidy boundaries around what they depict, and in the way a person charged with a criminal offence might complain that s/he “was framed” or “set up,” meaning that s/he didn’t do it.  The first sense indicates the way objects must be defined, conceptualised, bounded and brought into view in a particular light.  The second sense indicates the intrusive, active way in which concepts “produce” meanings, add meanings onto an object (an object does not necessarily mean anything independently of the concepts attributed to it) or even produce their object (an object may not exist independently of its concept, as is the case with Hamlet or the unicorn).  There is no alternative to the potentially criminal production of meanings, the risks we must take of “mis-representing” our objects; all theoretical work insists that concepts are created and used, and such use is always an addition and an intrusion.  So contemporary practices generally accept a responsibility not only for making their own backgrounds and presuppositions clear but also for questioning them, as I am doing in this chapter.  This questioning is not negative and destructive, as some people think, but is productive.  It develops concepts as it goes for theories that are intended to account for the very specific situations that require questioning in the first place, situations that are cultural and historical and thus always in a process of change as they fall inevitably into their unknown but often surprising future. 

Contemporary theory does not simply rely on past theoretical systems, developed say in philosophy, social theory, anthropology, linguistics, and textual criticism.  These must be used, certainly, because we have no already developed system of concepts that could possibly account for the situations that call for understanding and interpreting.  But theory too must be questioned and read in a carefully critical way, so we can use it to arrive at new conceptions, whilst as far as possible avoiding the deep seated prejudices that underlie all of our thinking (just by using available concepts we are making implicit judgments).  Thus theory operates on two levels.  On the level of objectivity, now understood as being impossible in any pure sense, we need to identify the situation that we are both conceptualising and intervening in.  On the level of conceptualisation itself, we must self-critically develop our concepts and arguments through careful readings of existing theory, locating contradictions and problems, and developing each time a workable framework for the specific engagement that we wish to make.

Contemporary theory cannot be thought of as belonging to any specific discipline.  Theory informs many disciplines, especially in moments of crisis and self-questioning, but it occurs generally as a process that is not reducible to any discipline (certainly not “its own” which would be a contradiction).  Theory puts the notion of a discipline under constant interrogation—not so traditions can be undermined in any naively subversive sense (although much contemporary theory is subversive)—but so traditions can be opened up to the possibility of their changing in productive ways, both in terms of their concepts and in terms of their activities, in short, their politics.  But while theory has its own mode of proceeding and must be regarded as operating outside the strict boundaries of existing disciplines, it cannot be thought of as existing simply independently of any discipline.  Theory is what happens when the grounds or the boundaries of disciplines are questioned and altered, certainly, but nothing like that could happen unless theoretical terms and concepts already existed.  And only traditional and everyday discourses have them.  If contemporary theory became an independent and autonomous discipline with its own philosophy and conceptual framework, it would no longer be theory but yet another discipline in the arts or social sciences, itself vulnerable to theoretical critique and resistant to anything perceived as “not belonging” within it.  In this respect it is instructive that the most influential authors, texts and arguments in contemporary theory consistently resist easy disciplinary categories.  A critical approach can work productively and often subversively within as well as between disciplines and traditions.

 

*  Summary

As I have shown, the problems that tax traditional theories in academic disciplines are general.  The difficulty of arriving at stable concepts that can accurately stand over against often enigmatic objects troubles all participation in everyday talk, as well as the discourses of the mass media and all practices that characterise a given culture.  And, just as the traditional sciences must ignore these difficulties in order to proceed, so too must the participants in everyday discourses ignore their own problematic grounds in order to get on with their lives.  What I am calling contemporary theory aims to expose those problematic grounds.  So concepts used in everyday discourses may be regarded as constructions, meanings that have been imposed on objects and which thus to an extent create those objects.  Everyday concepts, no less than those of a science, are specific ways of setting things in view, and framing them.  For participants in those discourses, however, these concepts will often appear natural or transparent.  In other words, only their objects will appear and they will appear is if independent of the system of concepts that has played such an important role in constructing the way that they appear.

 

One final observation now needs to be made.  Despite the need in academic disciplines for consensus, that is, a set of shared assumptions and definitions upon which practical and objective work may proceed, a brief history of any period in a discipline’s development will invariably reveal dispute and criticism at the deepest level.  If this is the case in science and philosophy, it is even more so in everyday discourse where meanings are by no means shared.  Meanings should be regarded as sites of constant struggle, which implies that a culture tends to be made up of individuals who are related only tentatively by shared values and norms, and those relations are often better characterised by mutual antagonism, incompatible interests, and struggles of power.  A concept in everyday discourse gets its naturalised sense only at the cost of other contradictory senses that would reveal it is historically and culturally overdetermined.

Lecturer:             Dr John Phillips

Phone:               874 3054

e mail:                elljwp@nus.edu.sg

 

Return to the Main Page on my Web Site: