Introduction and Methodology | 1 |
0.A. Introduction | 1 |
0.A.1. What this thesis is about | 1 |
0.A.2. Why write about living things? | 2 |
0.A.3. Why write about animals? | 3 |
0.A.4. What are animals? | 4 |
0.A.5. Why write about the moral entitlements of animals and other organisms? | 5 |
0.B Methodological proposals for this thesis | 7 |
0.B.1 What does it mean to be alive? | 9 |
0.B.2 Mental states in animals | 10 |
0.B.2(a) Is there a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for having a mind? | 10 |
0.B.2(b) What is the relationship between being alive and having a mind? | 11 |
0.B.2(c) What are the most primitive mental states? | 12 |
0.B.2(d) How do we identify the occurrence of primitive mental states? | 17 |
0.B.2(e) Emotions | 19 |
0.B.2(f) Phenomenally conscious mental states | 19 |
0.B.2(g) Higher-order mental states | 20 |
0.B.2(h) Drawing the Line | 21 |
0.B.2(i) How generous should we be in assessing claims for mental states? | 22 |
0.B.2(j) Appropriate Sources of Evidence | 23 |
0.B.2(j)(i) Singular versus replicable observations | 23 |
0.B.2(j)(ii) Laboratory versus natural observations | 24 |
0.B.3 Interests of Animals and Other Organisms | 25 |
0.B.3(a) Is my methodology ethically biased? | 26 |
0.B.3(b) What constraints should we impose on an ethical theory based on interests? | 26 |
0.B.3(c) How do we define and identify interests? | 26 |
0.B.3(d) The "is-ought" gap | 27 |
0.B.3(e) How do we resolve conflicts of interests between organisms? | 27 |
0.B.3(f) A general account of goodness | 28 |
Chapter 1 - What does it mean to be alive? | 28 |
1.A. An overview of attempts to define "life" | 28 |
1.A.0 Chapter summary | 28 |
1.A.1 Why does the distinction between living and non-living matter? | 28 |
1.A.2 A "conceptual map" of some historical positions taken in the debate about life | 31 |
1.A.3 Is there a crisis relating to the definition of "life"? | 42 |
1.A.3.1 Problems associated with the quest for single-attribute definitions of life | 43 |
1.A.3.2 Can cluster definitions work? | 47 |
1.A.3.2(a) Short cluster definitions | 49 |
1.A.3.2(b) Long cluster definitions | 52 |
1.A.3.3 Is it too soon to formulate a good definition? | 57 |
1.A.3.4 The new crisis regarding the definition of life | 58 |
1.A.3.5 What is wrong with the foregoing definitions of life? | 63 |
1.A.3.6 Is teleology redundant? | 66 |
1.A.3.7 Are there any good methodological reasons for rejecting teleological accounts of life? | 67 |
1.A.3.8 Is a teleological account of life intelligible? | 68 |
1.B. A proposed solution to the "problem of life": a "science-friendly" teleological account | 71 |
1.B.1 What distinguishes living things? | 74 |
1.B.2 Empirical formal and finalistic criteria for being alive | 81 |
1.B.3 Is my account of life reductionistic? | 73B |
1.B.4 Strong emergence, downward and backward causation | 77B |
1.B.5 Is the possession of intrinsic ends a sufficient and necessary condition for being alive? | 82B |
1.B.6. Does my account of life explain and unify all of the necessary conditions for something's being alive? | 90 |
1.B.6(a) Does my account of life unify the necessary conditions for something's being alive? | 90 |
1.B.6(b) What are the necessary conditions for something's being alive? | 95 |
1.B.7 What does it mean for a living thing to have a nature? | 96 |
1.B.8 Do living things have a privileged ethical status? | 106 |
Chapter 2 - What does it take to have a minimal mind? | 114 |
2.A How should we look for intentional agency in organisms? | 114 |
2.A.1. Preliminaries | 114 |
2.A.2. Mental states - Aristotelian, Cartesian and modern positions contrasted | 114 |
2.A.3. Conclusions reached - a note to the reader | 116 |
2.A.4 Wolfram's neo-animism: Are minds nothing more than computational devices? | 117 |
2.A.5 Dennett's intentional stance: Is mind a property of intentional systems? | 129 |
2.A.5(a) Has Dennett mis-described intentionality? | 129 |
2.A.5(b) Is Dennett's intentional stance a global theory of mental states? | 132 |
2.A.5(c) Is Dennett's intentional stance tied to reductionism? | 135 |
2.A.6 Why only living things can possess minds. Implications for artificial intelligence. | 140 |
2.A.7 Different kinds of intentional stance? Narrowing the search for mental states in organisms | 147 |
2.A.8 Biological processes that are best described using a goal-centred intentional stance | 151 |
2.A.9 Philosophical arguments against the possibility of belief in non-human animals | 153 |
2.B What does an organism need in order to possess a minimal mind? | 157 |
2.B.0 The Tree of Life - major groupings and relationships | 157 |
2.B.1 Sensory criteria for identifying mental states in organisms | 163 |
2.B.2 Memory-related criteria for attributing mental states to organisms | 177 |
2.B.3 Is flexible behaviour enough for having a mind? | 188 |
2.B.4 Learning-related criteria for attributing mental states to organisms | 203 |
2.B.4(a) Habituation and sensitization | 207 |
2.B.4(b) Associative learning | 218 |
2.B.4(c) Does associative learning qualify as learning, in the ordinary sense of the word? | 229 |
2.B.4(d) Does associative learning require a mentalistic explanation? | 231 |
2.B.5 Mind and movement - the significance of control in the identification of intentional agency | 245 |
2.B.5(a) Why internal states are important | 246 |
2.B.5(b) Does directed movement qualify as agency? | 248 |
2.B.5(c) Does navigation qualify as agency? | 253 |
2.B.5(d) Does having an action selection mechanism qualify as agency? | 258 |
2.B.5(e) The importance of fine-tuning for intentional agency | 266 |
2.B.6 Representations and mental states | 275 |
2.B.6(a) Why there can be no representation without the possibility of mis-representation | 275 |
2.B.6(b) Do Dretskean representations warrant the ascription of mental states to animals? | 279 |
2.B.7 Getting it wrong: the centrality of self-correction to belief | 287 |
2.B.7(a) Does associative learning require a mentalistic explanation? | 287 |
2.B.7(b) Does the phenomenon of blocking enable us to identify which animals have expectations? | 292 |
2.B.8 Synthesis: the ingredients of intentional agency | 295 |
2.C. Four models of a minimal mind | 298 |
2.C.1 A model of operant agency in insects | 298 |
2.C.2 Spatial learning, agency and belief in insects | 329 |
2.C.3 A model of tool agency in Cephalopods | 333 |
2.C.4 A model of social agency in fish | 334 |
2.D Higher kinds of learning in insects | 337 |
Chapter 3 - Animal Emotions | 338 |
3.0 Chapter outline | 338 |
3.1 Methodological Considerations | 340 |
3.1(a) Human Emotions cannot be defined apart from animal emotions | 340 |
3.1(b) General Properties of Emotions | 341 |
3.1(c) Animal emotions have intentional objects | 345 |
3.2 What are the cognitive pre-requisites of animal emotions? | 349 |
3.3 What are animal emotions "about", and what is each basic kind of animal emotion about? | 358 |
3.4 How do we identify basic emotions in animals, what are they and which animals can be said to have them? | 362 |
Chapter 4 - Animal Consciousness and Higher Mental States | 374 |
4.A. Phenomenal Consciousness in Animals | 374 |
4.1 What philosophers have to say about animal consciousness | 375 |
4.1.1 Philosophical distinctions regarding consciousness | 375 |
4.1.2 An outline of the current philosophical debate on animal consciousness | 383 |
4.2 Scientific findings regarding consciousness | 388 |
4.2.1 Primary versus "higher-order" consciousness | 388 |
4.2.2 Behavioural criteria for consciousness | 390 |
4.2.3 Neural pre-requisites for consciousness | 402 |
4.3 Ethical implications of animal consciousness | 420 |
4.B Evidence for rational agency in animals | 422 |
4.C Are non-human animals capable of moral agency? | 429 |
Chapter 5 - What are our duties towards other organisms? | 436 |
5.0 Chapter outline | 436 |
5.1 Which entities have moral standing? | 436 |
5.2 What duties do we have towards living things, and what is the basis for them? | 451 |
5.2.1 Duties owed to living things in general | 451 |
5.2.2 Duties owed to animals with minds | 453 |
5.2.3 Duties owed to companion animals (pets) | 469 |
5.2.4 Duties owed to human beings | 472 |
5.2.5 Duties pertaining to groups of organisms: greater wholes (e.g. ecosystems) and classes (e.g. species) | 478 |
Chapter 6 - What are we entitled to do vis-a-vis other organisms? | 482 |
6.0 Chapter outline | 482 |
6.1 Instrumentalism rejected | 483 |
6.2 The cardinal difficulty of biocentrism | 486 |
6.3 The deficiencies of a holistic ethic | 489 |
6.4 Vital, central and peripheral needs | 493 |
6.5 A Telos-Based Account of Entitlements and Justifiable Harms | 496 |
6.5(a) The Telos-Promoting Principle (TPP): which goods are we entitled to pursue? | 496 |
6.5(b) The Telos-Promoting Harm Principle (TPHP): which actions are we entitled to perform? | 498 |
6.6 Can harm done to other living things sometimes be justified on ecological grounds? | 525 |
Bibliography | 528 |
Appendices | 620 |
Appendix to chapter 1 | 620 |
Appendix to chapter 1 part A: Is teleology redundant? | 620 |
Appendix to chapter 1 part B: What are the necessary conditions for something's being alive? | 636 |
Appendix to chapter 2 | 662 |
Appendix to chapter 2 part A: Wolfram's neo-animism | 662 |
Appendix to chapter 2 part B: Criteria for having a minimal mind | 669 |
Some Background Information on the Five Kingdoms of Life | 671 |
1. Sensory criteria for identifying mental states in organisms | 684 |
1.1 Which organisms have sensors? | 684 |
1.2 Cotterill's arguments for denying true senses to bacteria | 690 |
1.3 Different kinds of senses in various kinds of living things | 693 |
2. Memory-related criteria for identifying mental states in organisms | 704 |
2.1 The Simplest kind of memory: chemical memory | 705 |
2.2 Problems relating to the definition of different kinds of memory | 709 |
2.3 Which organisms possess procedural, semantic and episodic memory? | 712 |
3. Is flexible behaviour enough for having a mind? | 715 |
3.1 How indirect, modifiable stimulus-coupling can still be a fixed pattern of behaviour | 715 |
3.2 Examples of so-called "flexible" behaviour which turn out to be fixed | 717 |
3.3 Fixed behaviour is compatible with multiple functions determining the value of the output variable | 720 |
3.4 Does flexible behaviour occur in bacteria? | 721 |
3.4.1 Cellular regulation in bacteria | 722 |
3.4.2 Phenotypic plasticity in bacteria | 725 |
3.4.3 Gene-swapping in bacteria: flexible behaviour? | 730 |
4. Is learning enough for having a mind? | 733 |
4.1 Are there any forms of learning more basic than habituation? | 733 |
4.2 Which organisms can undergo habituation and sensitization? | 735 |
4.3 Which organisms are capable of associative learning? | 742 |
4.4 Pavlov's model of associative conditioning compared with a contemporary model (Brembs, 1996) | 768 |
4.5 Three cases of associative learning without a brain which challenge Dretske's account of belief | 771 |
5. Mind and Movement - the significance of control in intentional agency | 776 |
5.1 Why random changes are insufficient for intentional agency | 777 |
5.2 Directed movement in organisms | 779 |
5.3 How animal cells see and move | 784 |
5.4 Case study: action selection in cnidaria | 788 |
5.5 Agency in cnidaria? | 792 |
5.6 Can cnidaria learn? | 795 |
5.7 Case study: centralised action selection in flatworms | 795 |
7. Getting it wrong: the centrality of self-correction to belief | 798 |
7.1 Is the phenomenon of blocking evidence of expectations in animals? | 798 |
7.2 Do higher-order forms of associative learning warrant an agent-centred intentional stance? | 804 |
Appendix to chapter 2 part C: Case studies | 812 |
1. Operant Agency | 814 |
1.1 Operant Agency in Drosophila melanogaster | 814 |
1.2 Merfeld's Model of Efference Copy | 822 |
1.3 Definition of Operant Agency | 824 |
2. Navigational Agency | 829 |
2.1 Definition of Navigational Agency | 829 |
2.2 Case study: Navigational Agency in Insects | 834 |
2.2(a) Is path integration a form of intentional agency? | 835 |
2.2(b) Is navigation by visual landmarks a form of intentional agency? | 839 |
2.2(c) Do insects use cognitive maps? | 846 |
2.3 Case study: Navigational Agency in Cephalopods | 850 |
3. Tool Agency | 853 |
3.1 Definition of Tool Agency | 853 |
3.2 Case study: Tool Agency in Cephalopods | 858 |
4. Social Agency | 866 |
4.1 Definition of Social Agency | 866 |
4.2 Case study: Social Agency in fish | 872 |
4.3 Case study: Evaluation of the evidence for Social Agency in octopuses | 885 |
5. A Special Case of Combined Agency in the Jumping Spider Portia | 888 |
Appendix to chapter 2 part D: Case studies of higher-order learning in insects | 891 |
1. Reversal Learning (an update on Gary Varner's claims regarding desire in animals) | 892 |
1.1 Rapid reversal learning in honeybees: evidence for the acquisition of beliefs? | 892 |
1.2 Is progressive adjustment in multiple reversal learning trials evidence for the acquisition of beliefs? | 895 |
2. Concept Formation in Insects | 897 |
2.1 Can honeybees form categorical concepts? | 898 |
2.2 Can honeybees form the concepts of "same" and "different"? | 902 |
Note: Higher-order learning in octopuses | 909 |
Appendix to Chapter 3 - Animal Emotions | 915 |
1. Should we stipulate consciousness as a requirement for having emotions? | 916 |
2. Is emotion fundamentally distinct from cognition? | 919 |
3. Do the basic emotions of fear, anger and desire presuppose a capacity for language? | 923 |
4. Can emotions be explained as bodily states? | 934 |
5. Deficient methodologies for distinguishing animal emotions | 939 |
6. What kinds of emotions do animals have? | 941 |
7. Which Animals Have Emotions? | 951 |
8. A general strategy for identifying occurrences of basic emotions in animals | 954 |
Appendix to Chapter 4 - Animal Consciousness and Higher Mental States | 963 |
Appendix to chapter 4 Part A - Phenomenal Consciousness | 963 |
1.1 Can access consciousness occur in the absence of phenomenal consciousness? | 964 |
1.2 Persistent Vegetative State: a case of behavioural wakefulness in the absence of phenomenal consciousness | 973 |
1.3 Evaluation of Carruthers' arguments against the occurrence of consciousness in non-human animals | 975 |
1.4 How the welfare of animals lacking phenomenal consciousness can be objectively assessed | 981 |
Appendix to chapter 4 part B - Higher-order consciousness and language in non-human animals? | 986 |
Appendix to chapter 5 | 993 |
Appendix to chapter 5 part A - Marginal Animal Cases | 993 |
Appendix to chapter 5 part B - Marginal Human Cases and their relevance for our duties towards animals | 1010 |
Appendix to chapter 6 | 1019 |
Appendix to chapter 6 part A - Do Animals and Other Organisms have Rights? | 1019 |
Appendix to chapter 6 part B - Practical Implications of TPHP | 1043 |