Back
to PHL 002 Home Page
Dr. Christian Perring
Dowling College
PHL 002 Western Philosophy 2
THE UTILITARIANS
Jeremy Bentham
-
Born in London, 1748. Son of a prosperous Tory. He trained
as a lawyer. But he was disgusted by the state of the law, and so set out
to criticize it rather than be a part of the legal profession.
-
In 1776 he published Fragment on Government, a criticism
of a legal commentary. This is where he first set out his utilitarian view.
-
In 1785 he went to Russia for 3 years.
-
In 1789 he published Introduction to the Principles of
Morals and Legislation, his most important philosophical work.
-
He designed a new model for a prison, the Panopticon. This
prison would be circular, so the warden could sit in the center and observe
all the prisoners. It was also be privatized.
-
He had many other practical suggestions, such as trains of
carts between London and Edinburgh, a Panama canal, and frozen peas.
-
In 1808, he met James Mill and his two year old son John
Stuart. The Mill family came to live near Bentham in London.
-
Until 1818, the Mill family spent six months of each year
with Bentham at Ford Abbey, in Somerset.
-
He worked steadily on proposals for legal reform and exposing
abuses of government during his lifetime.
-
He died in 1832.
John Stuart Mill (1806-1873)
-
Mill was a child prodigy. His father taught him Greek at
the age of 3 or 4. He started arithmetic and Latin at 8 years, logic at
12, political economy at 13. Until he was 14, he saw no one of his own
age, and mixed only with his father’s utilitarian friends. He was also
required to teach his younger brothers what he had learned from his father.
-
At the age of 14, he began to study law, but he gave it up
after 3 years. He became a clerk instead.
-
At the age of 20, he fell into a two year depression. He
attributed his recovery to his discovery of the poetry of Wordsworth.
-
In 1830 he met Harriet Taylor. They married in 1851, after
her first husband's death. She died of tuberculosis in 1858.
-
On Liberty was published in 1859, Utilitarianism
in 1861.
-
In 1865 he became a member of parliament for Westminster,
a borough of central London. He was a political liberal. He lost the next
election 3 years later.
-
The Subjection of Women was published in 1869.
-
He moved to France with his step-daughter Helen Taylor, and
died in 1873.
Utilitarianism
-
This theory says that when you are faced with different options,
morally speaking you should chose the one which will result in the most
happiness for society. "The greatest happiness for the greatest number."
-
Your own happiness should not count any more or any less
than anyone else's in your calculations.
-
This guide was meant to apply both to individual people
and also to governments.
Bentham on Government
-
The Utilitarians used their theory to argue for parliamentary
reform, prison reform, the extension of the right to vote, full legal rights
for women, greater democracy, ways of making government officials accountable,
and changes in punishment. In their day, the Utilitarians were seen as
radicals.
-
Bentham argued that punishment of criminals could only be
justified if it did more good than harm. Punishing criminals causes them
to be unhappy, and this must be added into the utilitarian calculation.
Punishment must deter crime if it is to be justified, and if two available
punishments have equal deterrence, then the lesser punishment must be chosen.
-
From his experience at trying to reform the prison system,
Bentham concluded that governments generally do not act in the people's
best interest, but instead act selfishly. He concluded that the people
should be able to vote on all decisions that affect them. The people, following
their own interests, will vote for what brings the greatest happiness to
the greatest number.
-
Bentham saw his work as the clarifying of ideas, such as
good and bad, rights and duties, and punishment. Clarifying these will
then clarify the law, and provide a secure foundation for it. Statements
about good and bad can be seen as translatable to statements about happiness
and unhappiness. Rights can be explained as corresponding to duties, and
duties can be explained as what you must do if you want to avoid punishment.
-
This goes with his rejection of the widely accepted "natural
law" theory -- the view that law and ethics are basically the same. "Natural
rights is simple nonsense: natural and imprescriptible rights, rhetorical
nonsense, nonsense upon stilts."
-
Bentham's view was that the law and ethics are very distinct
realms. The law should be ethical, but (unfortunately) it is not always
so. Laws are commands backed up by sanctions. The only rights
that he recognizes are legal rights, and these rights are justified because
they promote the general happiness. But they are not inalienable: if they
start to do more harm than good, then they should be abolished.
-
So he was critical of the justifications given for the American
and French Revolutions, which appealed to the "Rights of Man," although
he was sympathetic to the cause of the revolutionaries.
-
Similarly, Bentham was critical of social contract
theories. He thought that the only real contracts are legal ones. A legal
system must already exist for contracts to be possible, so the legal system
cannot be justified in terms of a contract. The only legitimate justification
of a legal system, in his view, is that it promotes the general happiness.
Bentham believed that governments should promote equality
among people, because this is the best way to increase the general happiness.
His main justification for this was that people who already have goods
get less happiness when they are given more of them than people who don't
have them in the first place. For instance, consider two possibilities:
I give everyone in the class (of 15 students) $10 each, or I give one person
in the class $150. Which will promote the most total happiness? The more
equal distribution.
Justifying Utilitarian Theory
-
Happiness comes in various kinds. The only realistic way
to measure happiness is in terms of pleasure and pain. There are pleasures
of sense, wealth, skill, a good reputation, piety, power, memories, and
so on. There are many kinds of pain too. Pleasure and pain can be described
in terms of their:
-
Intensity - how strong the feeling is.
-
Duration - how long the feeling will last
-
Avoidability - whether we can take steps to not feel pain.
-
Expected time of occurrence
-
Fecundity - how much further pleasure or pain come with them.
-
Purity (pleasure not mixed with pain)
-
Extent (how many people experience the pleasure or pain.)
-
All these factors should be taken into account in measuring
how good the effects of an action will be. The measurement can be somewhat
scientific, given in rough quantities.
-
A crucial disagreement among Utilitarians: Are there different
kinds of pleasure? Bentham said no: "quantity of pleasure being equal,
push-pin is as good as poetry." But Mill said yes: some pleasures are worth
more than others. (See Utilitarianism, Chapter 2.)
-
Different people will have different opinions about which
kinds of pleasure are best: when there is disagreement, the majority (of
experienced people who have knowledge of the comparison) should rule, according
to Mill.
-
Bentham and Mill agree that there is no simple way to prove
utilitarianism is the right moral theory, because it is a theory about
ultimate ends, and there is no disputing ultimate ends. It is the first
principle of morality, so there is no prior principle with which to prove
it.
-
But Bentham says that the only competitors to utilitarianism
are asceticism and sympathy, and both can be shown to be
inadequate.
-
Asceticism says that some actions which deny pleasures are
right. For example, self-denial. If it were really true that some actions
which do not maximize pleasure are the best ones, then utilitarianism would
be mistaken. However, Bentham observes that often the justification for
the rightness of such ascetic actions is that they will provide happiness
in the long run. For example, if I deny myself more food now, I will not
have a stomach ache later on. He also points out that asceticism makes
no sense when applied to government policy: we would never agree with a
government that caused public suffering unless it could show that the suffering
would lead to greater happiness in the long run.
-
Using sympathy to justify morality is to say that something
is right if people approve of it. Bentham says that this is totally arbitrary.
-
Mill argues against several objections to his Greatest Happiness
Principle.
-
Objection: Happiness is not possible.
-
Reply: Happiness is possible: it doesn't have to be
a constant state of elation; what we aim for is moments of rapture, "in
an existence made up of few and transitory pains, many and various pleasures,
with a decided predominance of the active over the passive, and having
as the foundation of the whole, not to expect more from life than it is
capable of bestowing." (U, Ch 2) People might not be happy now, but that
is due to the "present wretched education, and wretched social arrangements."
-
Objection: Utilitarianism expects too much of people.
-
Reply: A moral theory is meant to set standards of
behavior. It does not expect ordinary individuals to do more than they
can.
-
Objection: Utilitarianism would make people cold and
calculating in their actions.
-
Reply: Utilitarianism is not saying that morality
is the only important thing in life.
-
Objection: Utilitarianism is godless.
-
Reply: Utilitarianism may well be setting out God's
morality.
-
Objection: there often is not enough time to calculate
the happiness that will result from different options.
-
Reply: one might as well argue that one should not
be a Christian because there is no time to read the Bible before performing
an action. There is plenty of time to prepare for action, and formulate
subordinate principles.
-
Mill argues that the ultimate reason for believing in Utilitarianism
is that it is captures people's feelings. People do in fact care about
the general happiness. If there is one individual who does not share these
feelings, then the has no reason to accept Utilitarianism. (U, Ch. 3)
-
He does not know for certain whether the feelings are caused
by society or are innate, although he suspects that they are acquired.
Humans are capable of being brought up differently and having different
moral feelings. But having utilitarian feelings contributes to a society
without strife. People need to cooperate with each other, so it is natural
to care about each other's good.
Mill on Liberty
-
‘The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised
over any members of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent
harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient
warrant.’ (Ch. 1)
-
He is not applying his principle to children: there we can
decide what is good for them and force them to do what we decide.
-
‘Those who are still in a state to require being taken care
of by others, must be protected against their own actions as well as against
any external injury.’ (Ch. 1)
-
Mill gives two defenses of this principle of liberty. (These
both ultimately appeal to the Principle of Greatest Happiness.)
-
First that it enables individuals to realize their own individual
potential in their own way, and
-
second, by liberating talents, creativity, and dynamism,
it sets up the essential pre-condition for moral and intellectual progress.
-
For example, when it comes to freedom of expression, Mill
argues that no ideas should ever be stifled. "The peculiar evil of silencing
the expression of an opinion is, that it is robbing the human race." (Ch.
2)
-
If a person's opinion is right but silenced, then the person
loses the chance to correct everyone else.
-
If the person's opinion is wrong and silenced, she loses
the chance to learn the truth through debate.
-
It is only through having an open debate about issues that
we can have confidence in our ways for finding out what is true or false.
-
Although we should not prevent people from living how they
want to (so long as they do not harm others) that does not mean that we
should not express our opinions to them about their values and lifestyle.
-
What about difficult cases? E.g., gambling, drunkenness,
incontinence, idleness, or uncleanliness. (Ch. 4) These hurt other people,
not just the person who is living that lifestyle. Mill is ready to allow
interference in some of these cases: if someone neglects his family due
to drunkenness, then he should be punished. But he should be punished for
the neglect, not for drinking. He should equally be punished if he neglects
his family by spending too much time studying philosophy! "No person ought
to be punished simply for being drunk."
-
Even though society in general may be harmed by people not
taking care of themselves, those people should not be punished so long
as they do not harm particular individuals. Society has control over people
during their childhood, and if it cannot teach people to care for themselves
during that time, it has only itself to blame if people do not contribute
to society once they are adults.
-
The strongest argument that Mill has against society interfering
with people's behavior for their own good is that society will most likely
just make matters worse.
-
Some people say they have been injured simply by knowing
that other people behave in ways of which they don't approve. "But there
is no parity between the feeling of a person for his own opinion, and the
feeling of another who is offended at his holding it; no more than between
the desire of a thief to take a purse, and the desire of the right owner
to keep it. And a person's taste is as much is own particular concern as
his purse" (Ch. 4)