Site hosted by Angelfire.com: Build your free website today!

<< home  < Articles

The Monty Hall Problem 

Threads - Monty Hall Problem

On 16/1/2004,  Paul Williams posted:

I realise that many Science-Matters members may be familiar with this conundrum (below)
Nevertheless, I believe it needs to aired out again on ocassions.
I have still a carton of beer to collect from a good friend regarding his (incorrect) answer to this question. (He has a MSc and ocassionally advises me in mathematics - which I'm sadly deficient in)

O.K. Imagine that you are the contestant...
Should you switch doors or should you stay with your first choice - or does it make any difference?

Zero Sum replied:

We have had it out many times.  The best option is to change your choice.

> THE MONTY HALL PROBLEM
>
> "This story is true, and comes from an American tv game show. Here is
> the situation. Finalists in a tv game show are invited up onto the
> stage, where there are three closed doors. The host explains that behind
> one of the doors is the star prize - a car. Behind each of the other two
> doors is just a goat.
>
> Obviously the contestant wants to win the car, but does not know which
> door conceals the car.
> The host invites the contestant to choose one of the three doors. Let us
> suppose that our contestant chooses door number 3. Now, the host does
> not initially open the door chosen by the contestant. Instead he opens
> one of the other doors - let us say it is door number 1. The door that
> the host opens will always reveal a goat. Remember the host knows what
> is behind every door!
>
> The contestant is now asked if they want to stick with their original
> choice, or if they want to change their mind, and choose the other
> remaining door that has not yet been opened. In this case number 2. The
> studio audience shout suggestions. What is the best strategy for the
> contestant? Does it make any difference whether they change their mind
> or stick with the original choice? "

Peter Macinnis posted:

And as has been said before, if you can't see it, do a complete tree diagram.

John Winckle answered:

I have seen pages of statistical proof for this and someone actually ran trials with thousands of examples being run.
I think there is a  simple logical proof that it easier to understand.
When you make your initial choice you divide the three doors into two groups or sets.  The 'set of those doors that you chose' (one member) and 'the set of those you did not choose', (two members).
All doors have an equal chance of having the prize namely 33%
So 'the set of ones you chose' has 33% chance of winning. and 'the set of those you did not choose' has 67% chance of winning.
When the game show host eliminates one member of the 'set of those you did not choose' the odds of both sets remain the same.
The odds belong to the set not the individual members in it.
However now that there is only one member in 'the set of those you did not choose' if you  now choose that one your odds change from 33% chance to 67% chance, or double your chances.
There are some assumptions that are unstated.  One of these is that the game show host knows where the prize is.
How does that look?


Mijochelle (Jon Pearce) wrote:

Having given some thought to this (and I am no expert in maths or stats), it seems there are two distinct probability "events" here;

Firstly, when making the first choice, there is the 33% probability of getting it right. (One correct from 3 choices).

In the second event, the choices are reduced to 2, one right, one wrong.  Making a random choice at this point means a 50% chance of being correct.  So there is no "better" choice unless you possess ESP (if you believe in that sort of thing).

HOWEVER, if the host is ALWAYS going to reveal (and therefore eliminate) a wrong choice after your first choice, then the probability of eventually choosing the right door would always have been 50%, because as a linked event, one of the "wrong" choices will be eliminated, and you will always be left with a one in two choice.

To answer the original question, is there a benefit in changing your original choice, .. no, I don't think so.


Paul Williams responded:

The remaining 2 doors have 3 possibilities - Goat/Goat : Car/Goat : Goat/Car.
If you were to change doors now, with no help from the host, whichever door you changed to would have a 1 in 3 chance of winning.

> HOWEVER, if the host is ALWAYS going to reveal (and therefore eliminate)
> a wrong choice after your first choice, then the probability of
> eventually choosing the right door would always have been 50%, because
> as a linked event, one of the "wrong" choices will be eliminated, and
> you will always be left with a one in two choice.

Your first choice can *never change* from 1 in 3 odds.
The remaining doors *never change* from 2 in 3 odds.
So if you were given the choice of swapping your door for the other 2 doors it would double your odds of winning.
One of these doors, at least, will always hide a goat - the host eliminates one of these doors (hiding a goat) but he is still
effectivelygiving you the choice of swapping your one door for 2 doors.

> To answer the original question, is there a benefit in changing your
> original choice, .. no, I don't think so.

Let's say you always pick Door #1:

Door # 1   |   Door# 2 & Door # 3
Goat         |    Goat & Car
Car           |    Goat & Goat
Goat         |     Car & Goat

It can be clearly seen that staying with Door #1 will win the Car 1 in 3 times.
As a Door with a Goat is always eliminated from your remaining choices, it can be seen that changing your choice to the remaining door will win the car 2 in 3 times.

John Winckle explains this well (see below)
There is a set of 1 Door (your first choice) with a 33.3*% chance of winning.
There is a set of 2 Doors remaining, with a combined 66.6* chance of winning.
The second set is reduced to 1 Door which has a 66.6* chance of winning.
(The host always eliminates a door with a goat)

If there were 100 doors with 99 goats and one car:
Choosing one door gives you an *invariable* 1 in 100 chance of picking the car.
If you could change to the remaining doors, 99 times out of 100 you would win.
If the host eliminates 98 doors with goats, should you change doors?

David Maddern queried:

I can not handle how you come to the conclusion that "The remaining 2 doors have 3 possibilities - Goat/Goat : Car/Goat :
> Goat/Car."

When the host explains there is a car behind one of the doors and then opens one door to reveal a goat.
The resultant possibilities are (car / goat) and (goat / car) and since there is only one car there is a 50:50 chance of choosing the car   Which one you choose does not change the physical entities in front of you.  Which one you point at does not affect what is behind the doors. In that they are symmetrical.  Both remaining doors are equal.  It is not affected by you poining at it.

Also you say that "Your first choice can *never change* from 1 in 3 odds"
Surely it does when one door is opened.
As your degrees of freedom reduce from three to two the probability of your getting it right increases.
Same phenomenon as having got 4 lottery numbers marked off increases your chance of having won the big prize.  Of course you have already won or lost it as far as the lottery commission is concerned.

Your contention is that one door being revealed negatively changes the chance of the one already nominated negatively defies logic.

So what have I missed. Is there some double meaning somewhere?

Zero Sum answered:

> you. Which one you point at does not affect what is behind the doors. In
> that they are symettrical. Both remaining doors are equal. It is not
> effected by you poining at it.

No, but you 'point to' before the event.  The doors are not equal.  The chance is no 50:50.

> Also you say that "Your first choice can *never change* from 1 in 3
> odds" Surely it does when one door is opened.

Nope. Nothing has changed about your frst guess, its chances are still one in three.

> As your degrees of freedom reduce from three to two the probability of
> your getting it right increases.

And the choice was made before the any alteration in degrees of freedom so how can the probablility of you 'getting it right' change?

> Same phenomenon as having got 4 lottery numbers marked off increases
> your chance of having won the big prize. Of course you have already won
> or lost it as far as the lottery commission is concerned.

No. This is not the same case at all.

> Your contention is that one door being revealed negatively changes the
> chance of the one already nominated negatively defies logic.

Your contention that one door being revealed negativly can affect a
decision made in the past defies logic.

> So what have I missed. Is there some double meaning someqwhere?

Contingncy and he existence of time.

Draw a table.

Anthony Morton posted:

I suspect what's going on here is that most treatments of probability, even at advanced level, fail to stress the vital connection with information.  Instead, probability is taught as though it springs magically from the definition of an 'event space'.  As a result people are easily lulled into erroneous reasoning about problems like this one.

If you have a set of similar 'events' andyou have no information that could imply that one event is more likely than another, then and only then should you assign equal probability to each event, equal to the reciprocal of the number of 'degrees of freedom'.  This is what Laplace rather quaintly called the Principle of Insufficient Reason, and what modern authors call the 'principle of indifference'.

Unfortunately, the principle of indifference is invoked so frequently in applications that it's easy to imagine that it automatically applies in all situations, and much teaching of probability fails to point out that this is a fallacy.

So let's look at the Monty Hall problem again.  At the start you have three doors, one with a car inside and the other two with goats.  You don't have any reason to think one's more likely to contain the car than any other.  So when you choose one door, the probability you've picked the car is one-third.  No problem here.

Now Monty the host opens one of the other doors to reveal a goat.  Subsequent reasoning hinges on three crucial (but veiled) assumptions:
1. Unlike you, Monty knows where the car is.  So Monty doesn't have to work with probabilities; for him, the car is behind one door with probability one and behind the others with probability zero.  Yours and Monty's probabilities are different because you have different information.
2. Monty knows which door you chose, and can make his choice of door based on that knowledge.
3. You are to assume that Monty deliberately chose a door that he knew would reveal a goat.

As a result of (3), Monty has shared some of his information with you.
So you are no longer in a situation of zero information, and so you should no longer automatically assign probabilities based on the principle of indifference.

However, the new information you have is of a rather limited kind: it does not affect your degree of uncertainty about your initial choice.
This is because no matter what your initial choice was, Monty can always open a second door so as to reveal a goat.

This is a point better understood by enlarging the event space.  If you've blindly drawn a card from a 52-card deck, Monty can always look through the remaining 51 cards and show you 50 that are not the Ace of  Spades.  But regardless of this, the probability that you drew the Ace of Spades remains at 1/52: it does not magically jump to 1/2.

In each case, Monty has provided you with no information about your initial selection, but on the other hand has provided substantial information about the remaining alternative.  In the card analogy, Monty will have found the Ace of Spades among the 51 remaining cards with probability 51/52, and after revealing the other 50 cards will hold the Ace with this probability.  In the original problem, the car is behind one of the other two doors with probability 2/3, and Monty's opening of one door that he knew in advance would contain a goat does not change this probability.

This contrasts with the very different scenario where Monty opens a second door 'at random'.  What this really means is that he deliberately makes no use of whatever prior information he has.  (To ensure he really does this and doesn't cheat, it might be better to imagine he asks you, or an uninformed audience member, to choose the second door.)  Of the three assumptions above, only (2) is operative.

This puts Monty in exactly the same zero-information situation as you in your initial choice.  With probability 1/3, he will open the door with the car inside.

If Monty opens a second door 'at random' and it happens to have a goat inside, the situation looks superficially the same as in the real Monty Hall problem.  But there is a crucial difference: here it was not certain that Monty would reveal a goat.  In fact, the probability that the door would have a goat inside now depends on whether your initial choice was the car or a goat.  If you had chosen the car, the probability would be 1; if a goat, the probability would only be 1/2.  This means that the opening of the second door reveals some information about what's behind your door.  Thus, the probability you've chosen the car now changes from its 'a priori' value of 1/3 to a new 'a posteriori' value.

This new value can be determined from probability calculus.  Define the following propositions:
A: The door you chose has the car inside.
B: A second door opened at random reveals a goat.

I'll use a tilde to denote negation.  Thus initially, with no information, we have P(A) = 1/3 and P(~A) = 2/3.

The 'a posteriori' probability is P(A|B), the probability of A given B is true.  By the product rule of probability, this is equal to

        P(A|B) = P(AB) / P(B)

where P(AB) is the probability that both A and B are true.  This joint probability can be calculated using the product rule again:

        P(AB) = P(BA) = P(B|A) P(A) = 1 x 1/3 = 1/3

since if A is true, Monty could not help but reveal a goat: P(B|A) = 1.

We also need the probability P(B) that B is true, irrespective of the truth of A.  This is found using the 'rule of total probability' taught in high school:

        P(B) = P(B|A) P(A) + P(B|~A) P(~A).

We noted above that P(B|A) = 1 while P(B|~A) = 1/2. 

Thus
         P(B) = 1 x 1/3 + 1/2 x 2/3 = 2/3

and
        P(A|B) = P(AB) / P(B) = (1/3) / (2/3) = 1/2.

So here we have full agreement with intuition: if Monty opens a second door at random and it turns out to have a goat inside, the probability that you've chosen the car jumps from 1/3 to 1/2.  (On the other hand, if the second door turns out to have the car inside, your probability jumps from 1/3 to zero.)

What happens in the real Monty Hall problem?  Here we have not B but a new proposition C: A second door opened by Monty, who knows in advance there is a goat inside, reveals a goat.

Mathematically, what makes the difference here is that P(C|A) = P(C|~A) = 1; your initial choice doesn't affect Monty's ability to reveal a goat.  So we have

        P(AC) = P(C|A) P(A) = 1 x 1/3 = 1/3
        P(C) = P(C|A) P(A) + P(C|~A) P(~A) = 1 x 1/3 + 1 x 2/3 = 1
        P(A|C) = P(AC) / P(C) = (1/3) / 1 = 1/3.

So in the real Monty Hall problem, the fact that C is a logical certainty means that the a priori and a posteriori probabilities of A
are identical.

The TV show 'Deal Or No Deal' is a slightly more complex instance of the pseudo-Monty Hall problem.  Here the contestant makes an initial choice out of 24 briefcases and then eliminates alternatives herself.
Unlike the real Monty Hall situation, if the revealed alternatives turn out not to be the main $2 million prize, the probability the contestant is holding the $2 million really does go up each time; by the time there is only one alternative remaining the probability has increased from 1/24 to 1/2.  Clearly things would be very different if the alternatives were being eliminated by someone with prior information about which briefcase held the prize.

Mijochelle responded:

>The remaining 2 doors have 3 possibilities - Goat/Goat : Car/Goat :
>Goat/Car.

Sorry Peter, but there are now only TWO remaining possiblilities, Goat/Car - Car/Goat - The game show host ALWAYS opens the door of a Goat prize.  That "Choice" is logically presumed to be excluded, and thus eliminates the Goat/Goat option at that point.  Given that the Host ALWAYS opens a Goat door, it is always a choice of one door or the other.

I agree that at the start it is a 1 in three chance, but probability deals with chances, not certainties.  Once you introduce the certainty of an event, then the probability of that event is 1 to 1 (100%) (not 33%).  The remaining events then make up the probability.

John Winckle commented:

It is a puzzle. If the answer was as you say there would be no point to the puzzle. It is because it is so counter intuitive that it becomes so interesting. You are in good company but wrong.

David Maddern wrote:

Thank you Anthony for spending the time to explain this.

To my way of reconciling the world I agree that probability in this case is about information and is specific to each party (Monty vs observers). The probability we are talking about is "Of the choice made being revealed to be a car"

The way I see it Monty's intention does not change the physical presence behind the doors.
It is irrelevant what his intention is to the physical revelation of the goat to the observer, but there is now more information and half of the 2/3 probability of the two other doors is dispelled and the choice is now between 2 identical doors, so is 50:50 to the observers that the choice made be revealed to be a car .

The logical extension of your explanation is that any of the original doors has a dual probalility, and whichever one originally chosen will end up with less probability by virtue of being chosen.  Similarly if the choice is changed in the original three picture , that door then carries the less probability.  Hence each of the doors has a dual probability.
I dont think the world works that way, it is not that subject to human vicissitudes.

About the cards, if Monty is revealing each of the cards (like he did the goat) that arent the ace of spades then the final choice is between two cards, the one not in the pack and the ace, and that is 50:50. The probability of you originally choosing the ace is 1/52, but as possibles are discovered, the probability that you now have the ace rises.

Je vais a dormir

and

Yes, John but that is like saying someone is guilty because the cops have him.
Or God exists cos they wrote a book about him

Zero Sum wrote:

> The way I see it Monty's intention does not change the physical presence
> behind the doors.

The way you see it and the way the universe sees it are not the same.  I have a suspicion that the way the universe sees it is more important.

> It is irrelevant what his intention is to the physical revelation of the
> goat to the observer, but there is now more information and half of the
> 2/3 probability of the two other doors is dispelled and the choice is
> now between 2 identical doors, so is 50:50 to the observers that the
> choice made be revealed to be a car .

The two remaining doors are not identical any longer, they may be the same size and coulur but the information associated with the doors has changed.

> The logical extension of your explanation is that any of the original
> doors has a dual probalility, and whichever one originally chosen will
> end up with less probability by virtue of being chosen. Similarly if
> the choice is changed in the original three picture , that door then
> carries the less probability. Hence each of the doors has a dual
> probability.

You assert that this is a logical extension and then asume it as fact.  It  is neither logical nor would I call it an extension - a long stretch,  maybe.

> I dont think the world works that way, it is not that subject to human
> vicissitudes.

The world works the way it does and having an opinion on it is irrelevant.  If you don't accept the reasoning presented and won't draw a table the only  thing I can suggest is that you perform the experiment and see what
results you get.  That will demonstrate the way the world works.

> About the cards, if Monty is revealing each of the cards (like he did
> the goat) that arent the ace of spades then the final choice is between
> two cards, the one not in the pack and the ace, and that is 50:50. The
> probability of you originally choosing the ace is 1/52, but as possibles
> are discovered, the probability that you now have the ace rises.

Please demonstrate how this occurs.  Since it does not, you have  Buckley's...

Oh, and I would love to play cards with you if you are wealthy...