Copy from one, it's plagiarism; copy from two, it's research. Wilson Mizner
Chapter 6: Difficulties of the Theory
By: Charles Darwin, 1859
LONG before the reader has arrived at this part of my work, a
crowd of difficulties will have occurred to him. Some of them are so
serious that to this day I can hardly reflect on them without being in
some degree staggered; but, to the best of my judgment, the greater
number are only apparent, and those that are real are not, I think,
fatal to the theory.
These difficulties and objections may be classed under the following
heads:- First, why, if species have descended from other species by
fine gradations, do we not everywhere see innumerable transitional
forms? Why is not all nature in confusion, instead of the species
being, as we see them, well defined?
Secondly, is it possible that an animal having, for instance, the
structure and habits of a bat, could have been formed by the
modification of some other animal with widely different habits and
structure? Can we believe that natural selection could produce, on the
one hand, an organ of trifling importance, such as the tail of a
giraffe, which serves as a fly-flapper, and, on the other hand, an
organ so wonderful as the eye?
Thirdly, can instincts be acquired and modified through natural
selection? What shall we say to the instinct which leads the bee to
make cells, and which has practically anticipated the discoveries of
profound mathematicians?
Fourthly, how can we account for species, when crossed, being
sterile and producing sterile offspring, whereas, when varieties are
crossed, their fertility is unimpaired?
The two first heads will here be discussed; some miscellaneous
objections in the following chapter; Instinct and Hybridism in the two
succeeding chapters.
On the Absence or Rarity of Transitional Varieties.
As natural
selection acts solely by the preservation of profitable modifications,
each new form will tend in a fully-stocked country to take the place
of, and finally to exterminate, its own less improved parent-form
and other less favoured forms with which it comes into competition.
Thus extinction and natural selection go hand in hand. Hence, if we
look at each species as descended from some unknown form, both the
parent and all the transitional varieties will generally have been
exterminated by the very process of the formation and perfection of
the new form.
But, as by this theory innumerable transitional forms must have
existed, why do we not find them embedded in countless numbers in
the crust of the earth? It will be more convenient to discuss this
question in the chapter on the Imperfection of the Geological
Record; and I will here only state that I believe the answer mainly
lies in the record being incomparably less perfect than is generally
supposed. The crust of the earth is a vast museum; but the natural
connections have been imperfectly made, and only at long intervals
of time.
But it may be urged that when several closely-allied species inhabit
the same territory, we surely ought to find at the present time many
transitional forms. Let us take a simple case: in travelling from
north to south over a continent, we generally meet at successive
intervals with closely allied or representative species, evidently
filling nearly the same place in the natural economy of the land.
These representative species often meet and interlock; and as the
one becomes rarer and rarer, the other becomes more and more frequent,
till the one replaces the other. But if we compare these species where
they intermingle, they are generally as absolutely distinct from
each other in every detail of structure as are specimens taken from
the metropolis inhabited by each. By my theory these allied species
are descended from a common parent; and during the process of
modification, each has become adapted to the conditions of life of its
own region, and has supplanted and exterminated its original
parent-form and all the transitional varieties between its past and
present states. Hence we ought not to expect at the present time to
meet with numerous transitional varieties in each region, though
they must have existed there, and may be embedded there in a fossil
condition. But in the intermediate region, having intermediate
conditions of life, why do we not now find closely-linking
intermediate varieties? This difficulty for a long time quite
confounded me. But I think it can be in large part explained.
In the first place we should be extremely cautious in inferring,
because an area is now continuous, that it has been continuous
during a long period. Geology would lead us to believe that most
continents have been broken up into islands even during the later
tertiary periods; and in such islands distinct species might have been
separately formed without the possibility of intermediate varieties
existing in the intermediate zones. By changes in the form of the land
and of climate, marine areas now continuous must often have existed
within recent times in a far less continuous and uniform condition
than at present. But I will pass over this way of escaping from the
difficulty; for I believe that many perfectly defined species have
been formed on strictly continuous areas; though I do not doubt that
the formerly broken condition of areas now continuous, has played an
important part in the formation of new species, more especially with
freely-crossing and wandering animals.
In looking at species as they are now distributed over a wide
area, we generally find them tolerably numerous over a large
territory, then becoming somewhat abruptly rarer and rarer on the
confines, and finally disappearing. Hence the neutral territory
between two representative species is generally narrow in comparison
with the territory proper to each. We see the same fact in ascending
mountains, and sometimes it is quite remarkable how abruptly, as Alph.
de Candolle has observed, a common alpine species disappears. The same
fact has been noticed by E. Forbes in sounding the depths of the sea
with the dredge. To those who look at climate and the physical
conditions of life as the all-important elements of distribution,
these facts ought to cause surprise, as climate and height or depth
graduate away insensibly. But when we bear in mind that almost every
species, even in its metropolis, would increase immensely in
numbers, were it not for other competing species; that nearly all
either prey on or serve as prey for others; in short, that each
organic being is either directly or indirectly related in the most
important manner to other organic beings,- we see that the range of
the inhabitants of any country by no means exclusively depends on
insensibly changing physical conditions, but in a large part on the
presence of other species, on which it lives, or by which it is
destroyed, or with which it comes into competition; and as these
species are already defined objects, not blending one into another
by insensible gradations, the range of any one species, depending as
does on the range of others, will tend to be sharply defined.
Moreover, each species on the confines of its range, where it exists
in lessened numbers, will, during fluctuations in the number of its
enemies or of its prey, or in the nature of the seasons, be
extremely liable to utter extermination; and thus its geographical
range will come to be still more sharply defined.
As allied or representative species, when inhabiting a continuous
area, are generally distributed in such a manner that each has a
wide range, with a comparatively narrow neutral territory between
them, in which they become rather suddenly rarer and rarer; then, as
varieties do not essentially differ from species, the same rule will
probably apply to both; and if we take a varying species inhabiting
a very large area, we shall have to adapt two varieties to two large
areas, and a third variety to a narrow intermediate zone. The
intermediate variety, consequently, will exist in lesser numbers
from inhabiting a narrow and lesser area; and practically, as far as I
can make out, this rule holds good with varieties in a state of
nature. I have met with striking instances of the rule in the case
of varieties intermediate between well-marked varieties in the genus
Balanus. And it would appear from information given me by Mr.
Watson, Dr. Asa Gray, and Mr. Wollaston, that generally, when
varieties intermediate between two other forms occur, they are much
rarer numerically than the forms which they connect. Now, if we may
trust these facts and inferences, and conclude that varieties
linking two other varieties together generally have existed in
lesser numbers than the forms which they connect, then we can
understand why intermediate varieties should not endure for very
long periods:- why, as a general rule, they should be exterminated and
disappear, sooner than the forms which they originally linked
together.
For any form existing in lesser numbers would, as already
remarked, run a greater chance of being exterminated than one existing
in large numbers; and in this particular case the intermediate form
would be eminently liable to the inroads of closely-allied forms
existing on both sides of it. But it is a far more important
consideration, that during the process of further modification, by
which two varieties are supposed to be converted and perfected into
two distinct species, the two which exist in larger numbers, from
inhabiting larger areas, will have a great advantage over the
intermediate variety, which exists in smaller numbers in a narrow
and intermediate zone. For forms existing in larger numbers will
have a better chance, within any given period, of presenting further
favourable variations for natural selection to seize on, than will the
rarer forms which exist in lesser numbers. Hence, the more common
forms, in the race for life, will tend to beat and supplant the less
common forms, for these will be more slowly modified and improved.
It is the same principle which, as I believe, accounts for the
common species in each country, as shown in the second chapter,
presenting on an average a greater number of well-marked varieties
than do the rarer species. I may illustrate what I mean by supposing
three varieties of sheep to be kept, one adapted to an extensive
mountainous region; a second to a comparatively narrow, hilly tract;
and a third to the wide plains at the base; and that the inhabitants
are all trying with equal steadiness and skill to improve their stocks
by selection; the chances in this case will be strongly in favour of
the great holders on the mountains or on the plains, improving their
breeds more quickly than the small holders on the intermediate narrow,
hilly tract; and consequently the improved mountain or plain breed
will soon take the place of the less improved hill breed; and thus the
two breeds, which originally existed in greater numbers, will come
into close contact with each other, without the interposition of the
supplanted, intermediate hill variety.
To sum up, I believe that species come to be tolerably
well-defined objects, and do not at any one period present an
inextricable chaos of varying and intermediate links; first, because
new varieties are very slowly formed, for variation is a slow process,
and natural selection can do nothing until favourable individual
differences or variations occur, and until a place in the natural
polity of the country can be better filled by some modification of
some one or more of its inhabitants. And such new places will depend
on slow changes of climate, or on the occasional immigration of new
inhabitants, and, probably, in a still more important degree, on
some of the old inhabitants becoming slowly modified, with the new
forms thus produced, and the old ones acting and reacting on each
other. So that, in any one region and at any one time, we ought to see
only a few species presenting slight modifications of structure in
some degree permanent; and this assuredly we do see.
Secondly, areas now continuous must often have existed within the
recent period as isolated portions, in which many forms, more
especially amongst the classes which unite for each birth and wander
much, may have separately been rendered sufficiently distinct to
rank as representative species. In this, case, intermediate
varieties between the several representative species and their
common parent, must formerly have existed within each isolated portion
of the land, but these links during the process of natural selection
will have been supplanted and exterminated, so that they will no
longer be found in a living state.
Thirdly, when two or more varieties have been formed in different
portions of a strictly continuous area, intermediate varieties will,
it is probable, at first have been formed in the intermediate zones,
but they will generally have had a short duration. For these
intermediate varieties will, from reasons already assigned (namely
from what we know of the actual distribution of closely allied or
representative species, and likewise of acknowledged varieties), exist
in the intermediate zones in lesser numbers than the varieties which
they tend to connect. From this cause alone the intermediate varieties
will be liable to accidental extermination; and during the process
of further modification through natural selection, they will almost
certainly be beaten and supplanted by the forms which they connect;
for these from existing in greater numbers will, in the aggregate,
present more varieties, and thus be further improved through natural
selection and gain further advantages.
Lastly, looking not to any one time, but to all time, if my theory
be true, numberless intermediate varieties, linking closely together
all the species of the same group, must assuredly have existed; but
the very process of natural selection constantly tends, as has been so
often remarked, to exterminate the parent-forms and the intermediate
links. Consequently evidence of their former existence could be
found only amongst fossil remains, which are preserved, as we shall
attempt to show in a future chapter, in an extremely imperfect and
intermittent record.
On the Origin and Transitions of Organic Beings with peculiar Habits
and Structure.- It has been asked by the opponents of such views as
I hold, how, for instance, could a land carnivorous animal have been
converted into one with aquatic habits; for how could the animal in
its transitional state have subsisted? It would be easy to show that
there now exist carnivorous animals presenting close intermediate
grades from strictly terrestrial to aquatic habits; and as each exists
by a struggle for life, it is clear that each must be well adapted
to its place in nature. Look at the Mustela vision of North America,
which has webbed feet, and which resembles an otter in its fur,
short legs, and form of tail. During the summer this animal dives
for and preys on fish, but during the long winter it leaves the frozen
waters, and preys, like other pole-cats, on mice and land animals.
If a different case had been taken, and it had been asked how an
insectivorous quadruped could possibly have been converted into a
flying bat, the question would have been far more difficult to answer.
Yet I think such difficulties have little weight.
Here, as on other occasions, I lie under a heavy disadvantage,
for, out of the many striking cases which I have collected, I can only
give one or two instances of transitional habits and structures in
allied species; and of diversified habits, either constant or
occasional, in the same species. And it seems to me that nothing
less than a long list of such cases is sufficient to lessen the
difficulty in any particular case like that of the bat.
Look at the family of squirrels; here we have the finest gradation
from animals with their tails only slightly flattened, and from
others, as Sir J. Richardson has remarked, with the posterior part
of their bodies rather wide and with the skin on their flanks rather
full, to the so-called flying squirrels; and flying squirrels have
their limbs and even the base of the tail united by a broad expanse of
skin, which serves as a parachute and allows them to glide through the
air to an astonishing distance from tree to tree. We cannot doubt that
each structure is of use to each kind of squirrel in its own
country, by enabling it to escape birds or beasts of prey, to
collect food more quickly, or, as there is reason to believe, to
lessen the danger from occasional falls. But it does not follow from
this fact that the structure of each squirrel is the best that it is
possible to conceive under all possible conditions. Let the climate
and vegetation change, let other competing rodents or new beasts of
prey immigrate, or old ones become modified, and all analogy would
lead us to believe that some at least of the squirrels would
decrease in numbers or become exterminated, unless they also become
modified and improved in structure in a corresponding manner.
Therefore, I can see no difficulty, more especially under changing
conditions of life, in the continued preservation of individuals
with fuller and fuller flank membranes, each modification being,
useful, each being propagated, until, by the accumulated effects of
this process of natural selection, a perfect so-called flying squirrel
was produced.
Now look at the Galeopithecus or so-called flying lemur, which
formerly was ranked amongst bats, but is now believed to belong to the
Insectivora. An extremely wide flank membrane stretches from the
corners of the jaw to the tail, and includes the limbs with the
elongated fingers. This flank-membrane is furnished with an extensor
muscle. Although no graduated links of structure, fitted for gliding
through the air, now connect the Galeopithecus with the other
Insectivora, yet there is no difficulty in supposing that such links
formerly existed, and that each was developed in the same manner as
with the less perfectly gliding squirrels; each grade of structure
having been useful to its possessor. Nor can I see any insuperable
difficulty in further believing that the membrane connected fingers
and fore-arm of the Galeopithecus might have been greatly lengthened
by natural selection; and this, as far as the organs of flight are
concerned, would have converted the animal into a bat. In certain bats
in which the wing-membrane extends from the top of the shoulder to the
tail and includes the hind-legs, we perhaps see traces of an apparatus
originally fitted for gliding through the air rather than for flight.
If about a dozen genera of birds were to become extinct, who would
have ventured to surmise that birds might have existed which used
their wings solely as flappers, like the logger-headed duck
(Micropterus of Eyton); as fins in the water and as front-legs on
the land, like the penguin; as sails, like the ostrich; and
functionally for no purpose, like the Apteryx? Yet the structure of
each of these birds is good for it, under the conditions of life to
which it is exposed, for each has to live by a struggle; but it is not
necessarily the best possible under all possible conditions. It must
not be inferred from these remarks that any of the grades of
wing-structure here alluded to, which perhaps may all be the result of
disuse, indicate the steps by which birds actually acquired their
perfect power of flight; but they serve to show what diversified means
of transition are at least possible.
Seeing that a few members of such water-breathing classes as the
Crustacea and Mollusca are adapted to live on the land; and seeing
that we have flying birds and mammals, flying insects of the most
diversified types, and formerly had flying reptiles, it is conceivable
that flying-fish, which now glide far through the air, slightly rising
and turning by the aid of their fluttering fins, might have been
modified into perfectly winged animals. If this had been effected, who
would have ever imagined that in an early transitional state they
had been the inhabitants of the open ocean, and had used their
incipient organs of flight exclusively, as far as we know, to escape
being devoured by other fish?
When we see any structure highly perfected for any particular habit,
as the wings of a bird for flight, we should bear in mind that animals
displaying early transitional grades of the structure will seldom have
survived to the present day, for they will have been supplanted by
their successors, which were gradually rendered more perfect through
natural selection. Furthermore, we may conclude that transitional
states between structures fitted for very different habits of life
will rarely have been developed at an early period in great numbers
and under many subordinate forms. Thus, to return to our imaginary
illustration of the flying-fish, it does not seem probable that fishes
capable of true flight would have been developed under many
subordinate forms, for taking prey of many kinds in many ways, on
the land and in the water, until their organs of flight had come to
a high stage of perfection, so as to have given them a decided
advantage over other animals in the battle for life. Hence the
chance of discovering species with transitional grades of structure in
a fossil condition will always be less, from their having existed in
lesser numbers, than in the case of species with fully developed
structures.
I will now give two or three instances both of diversified and of
changed habits in the individuals of the same species. In either
case it would be easy for natural selection to adapt the structure
of the animal to its changed habits, or exclusively to one of its
several habits. It is, however, difficult to decide, and immaterial
for us, whether habits generally change first and structure
afterwards; or whether slight modifications of structure lead to
changed habits; both probably often occurring almost simultaneously.
Of cases of changed habits it will suffice merely to allude to that of
the many British insects which now feed on exotic plants, or
exclusively on artificial substances. Of diversified habits
innumerable instances could be given: I have often watched a tyrant
flycatcher (Saurophagus sulphuratus) in South America, hovering over
one spot and then proceeding to another, like a kestrel, and at
other times standing stationary on the margin of water, and then
dashing into it like a kingfisher at a fish. In our own country the
larger titmouse (Parus major) may be seen climbing branches, almost
like a creeper; it sometimes, like a shrike, kills small birds by
blows on the head; and I have many times seen and heard it hammering
the seeds of the yew on a branch, and thus breaking them like a
nuthatch. In North America the black bear was seen by Hearne
swimming for hours with widely open mouth, thus catching, almost
like a whale, insects in the water.
As we sometimes see individuals following habits different from
those proper to their species and to the other species of the same
genus, we might expect that such individuals would occasionally give
rise to new species, having anomalous habits, and with their structure
either slightly or considerably modified from that of their type.
And such instances occur in nature. Can a more striking instance of
adaptation be given than that of a woodpecker for climbing trees and
seizing insects in the chinks of the bark? Yet in North America
there are woodpeckers which feed largely on fruit, and others with
elongated wings which chase insects on the wing. On the plains of La
Plata, where hardly a tree grows, there is a woodpecker (Colaptes
campestris) which has two toes before and two behind, a long pointed
tongue, pointed tail-feathers, sufficiently stiff to support the
bird in a vertical position on a post, but not so stiff as in the
typical woodpeckers, and a straight strong beak. The beak, however, is
not so straight or so strong as in the typical woodpeckers, but it
is strong enough to bore into wood. Hence this Colaptes in all the
essential parts of its structure is a woodpecker. Even in such
trifling characters as the colouring, the harsh tone of the voice, and
undulatory flight, its close blood-relationship to our common
woodpecker is plainly declared; yet, as I can assert, not only from my
own observation, but from those of the accurate Azara, in certain
large districts it does not climb trees, and it makes its nest in
holes in banks! In certain other districts, however, this same
woodpecker, as Mr. Hudson states, frequents trees, and bores holes
in the trunk for its nest. I may mention as another illustration of
the varied habits of this genus, that a Mexican Colaptes has been
described by De Saussure as boring holes into hard wood in order to
lay up a store of acorns.
Petrels are the most aerial and oceanic of birds, but in the quiet
sounds of Tierra del Fuego, the Puffinuria berardi, in its general
habits, in its astonishing power of diving, in its manner of
swimming and of flying when made to take flight, would be mistaken
by any one for an auk or a grebe; nevertheless it is essentially a
petrel, but with many parts of its organisation profoundly modified in
relation to its new habits of life; whereas the woodpecker of La Plata
has had its structure only slightly modified. In the case of the
waterouzel, the acutest observer by examining its dead body would
never have suspected its subaquatic habits; yet this bird, which is
allied to the thrush family, subsists by diving- using its wings under
water, and grasping stones with its feet. All the members of the great
order of hymenopterous insects are terrestrial excepting the genus
Proctotrupes, which Sir John Lubbock has discovered to be aquatic in
its habits; it often enters the water and dives about by the use not
of its legs but of its wings, and remains as long as four hours
beneath the surface; yet it exhibits no modification in structure in
accordance with its abnormal habits.
He who believes that each being has been created as we now see it,
must occasionally have felt surprise when he has met with an animal
having habits and structure not in agreement. What can be plainer than
that the webbed feet of ducks and geese are formed for swimming? Yet
there are upland geese with webbed feet which rarely go near the
water; and no one except Audubon has seen the frigate-bird, which
has all its four toes webbed, alight on the surface of the ocean. On
the other hand, grebes and coots are eminently aquatic, although their
toes are only bordered by membrane. What seems plainer than that the
long toes, not furnished with membrane, of the Grallatores are
formed for walking over swamps and floating plants?- the water-hen and
landrail are members of this order, yet the first is nearly as aquatic
as the coot, and the second nearly as terrestrial as the quail or
partridge. In such cases, and many others could be given, habits
have changed without a corresponding change of structure. The webbed
feet of the upland goose may be said to have become almost rudimentary
in function, though not in structure. In the frigate-bird, the
deeply scooped membrane between the toes shows that structure has
begun to change.
He who believes in separate and innumerable acts of creation may
say, that in these cases it has pleased the Creator to cause a being
of one type to take the place of one belonging to another type; but
this seems to me only re-stating the fact in dignified language. He
who believes in the struggle for existence and in the principle of
natural selection, will acknowledge that every organic being is
constantly endeavouring to increase in numbers; and that if any one
being varies ever so little, either in habits or structure, and thus
gains an advantage over some other inhabitant of the same country,
it will seize on the place of that inhabitant, however different
that may be from its own place. Hence it will cause him no surprise
that there should be geese and frigatebirds with webbed feet, living
on the dry land and rarely alighting on the water; that there should
be long-toed corncrakes, living in meadows instead of in swamps;
that there should be woodpeckers where hardly a tree grows; that there
should be diving thrushes and diving Hymenoptera, and petrels with the
habits of auks.
Organs of extreme Perfection and Complication
To suppose that the eye with all its inimitable contrivances for
adjusting the focus to different distances, for admitting different
amounts of light, and for the correction of spherical and chromatic
aberration, could have been formed by natural selection, seems, I
freely confess, absurd in the highest degree. When it was first said
that the sun stood still and the world turned round, the common
sense of mankind declared the doctrine false; but the old saying of
Vox populi, vox Dei, as every philosopher knows, cannot be trusted
in science. Reason tells me, that if numerous gradations from a simple
and imperfect eye to one complex and perfect can be shown to exist,
each grade being useful to its possessor, as is certainly the case; if
further, the eye ever varies and the variations be inherited, as is
likewise certainly the case and if such variations should be useful to
any animal under changing conditions of life, then the difficulty of
believing that a perfect and complex eye could be formed by natural
selection, though insuperable by our imagination, should not be
considered as subversive of the theory. How a nerve comes to be
sensitive to light, hardly concerns us more than how life itself
originated; but I may remark that, as some of the lowest organisms, in
which nerves cannot be detected, are capable of perceiving light, it
does not seem impossible that certain sensitive elements in their
sarcode should become aggregated and developed into nerves, endowed
with this special sensibility.
In searching for the gradations through which an orgain in any
species has been perfected, we ought to look exclusively to its lineal
progenitors; but this is scarcely ever possible, and we are forced
to look to other species and genera of the same group, that is to
the collateral descendants from the same parent-form, in order to
see what gradations are possible, and for the chance of some
gradations having been transmitted in an unaltered or little altered
condition. But the state of the same organ in distinct classes may
incidentally throw light on the steps by which it has been perfected.
The simplest organ which can be called an eye consists of an optic
nerve, surrounded by pigment-cells, and covered by translucent skin,
but without any lens or other refractive body. We may, however,
according to M. Jourdain, descend even a step lower and find
aggregates of pigment-cells, apparently serving as organs of vision,
without any nerves, and resting merely on sarcodic tissue. Eyes of the
above simple nature are not capable of distinct vision, and serve only
to distinguish light from darkness. In certain star-fishes, small
depressions in the layer of pigment which surrounds the nerve are
filled, as described by the author just quoted, with transparent
gelatinous matter, projecting with a convex surface, like the cornea
in the higher animals. He suggests that this serves not to form an
image, but only to concentrate the luminous rays and render their
perception more easy. In this concentration of the rays we gain the
first and by far the most important step towards the formation of a
true, picture-forming eye; for we have only to place the naked
extremity of the optic nerve, which in some of the lower animals
lies deeply buried in the body, and in some near the surface, at the
right distance from the concentrating apparatus, and an image will
be formed on it.
In the great class of the Articulata, we may start from an optic
nerve simply coated with pigment, the latter sometimes forming a
sort of pupil, but destitute of a lens or other optical contrivance.
With insects it is now known that the numerous facets on the cornea of
their great compound eyes form true lenses, and that the cones include
curiously modified nervous filaments. But these organs in the
Articulata are so much diversified that Muller formerly made three
main classes with seven subdivisions, besides a fourth main class of
aggregated simple eyes.
When we reflect on these facts, here given much too briefly, with
respect to the wide, diversified, and graduated range of structure
in the eyes of the lower animals; and when we bear in mind how small
the number of all living forms must be in comparison with those
which have become extinct, the difficulty ceases to be very great in
believing that natural selection may have converted the simple
apparatus of an optic nerve, coated with pigment and invested by
transparent membrane, into an optical instrument as perfect as is
possessed by any member of the articulate class.
He who will go thus far, ought not to hesitate to go one step
further, if he finds on finishing this volume that large bodies of
facts, otherwise inexplicable, can be explained by the theory of
modification through natural selection; he ought to admit that a
structure even as perfect as an eagle's eye might thus be formed,
although in this case he does not know the transitional states. It has
been objected that in order to modify the eye and still preserve it as
a perfect instrument, many changes would have to be effected
simultaneously, which, it is assumed, could not be done through
natural selection; but as I have attempted to show in my work on the
variation of domestic animals, it is not necessary to suppose that the
modifications were all simultaneous, if they were extremely slight and
gradual. Different kinds of modification would, also, serve for the
same general purpose: as Mr. Wallace has remarked, "if a lens has
too short or too long a focus, it may be amended either by an
alteration of curvature, or an alteration of density; if the curvature
be irregular, and the rays do not converge to a point, then any
increased regularity of curvature will be an improvement. So the
contraction of the iris and the muscular movements of the eye are
neither of them essential to vision, but only improvements which might
have been added and perfected at any stage of the construction of
the instrument." Within the highest division of the animal kingdom,
namely, the Vertebrata, we can start from an eye so simple, that it
consists, as in the lancelet, of a little sack of transparent skin,
furnished with a nerve and lined with pigment, but destitute of any
other apparatus. In fishes and reptiles, as Owen has remarked, "the
range of gradations of dioptric structures is very great." It is a
significant fact that even in man, according to the high authority
of Virchow, the beautiful crystalline lens is formed in the embryo
by an accumulation of epidermic cells, lying in a sack-like fold of
the skin; and the vitreous body is formed from embryonic sub-cutaneous
tissue. To arrive, however, at a just conclusion regarding the
formation of the eye, with all its marvellous yet not absolutely
perfect characters, it is indispensable that the reason should conquer
the imagination; but I have felt the difficulty far too keenly to be
surprised at others hesitating to extend the principle of natural
selection to so startling a length.
It is scarcely possible to avoid comparing the eye with a telescope.
We know that this instrument has been perfected by the
long-continued efforts of the highest human intellects; and we
naturally infer that the eye has been formed by a somewhat analogous
process. But may not this inference be presumptuous? Have we any right
to assume that the Creator works by intellectual powers like those
of man? If we must compare the eye to an optical instrument, we
ought in imagination to take a thick layer of transparent tissue, with
spaces filled with fluid, and with a nerve sensitive to light beneath,
and then suppose every part of this layer to be continually changing
slowly in density, so as to separate into layers of different
densities and thicknesses, placed at different distances from each
other, and with the surfaces of each layer slowly changing in form.
Further we must suppose that there is a power, represented by
natural selection or the survival of the fittest, always intently
watching each slight alteration in the transparent layers; and
carefully preserving each which, under varied circumstances, in any
way or in any degree, tends to produce a distincter image. We must
suppose each new state of the instrument to be multiplied by the
million; each to be preserved until a better one is produced, and then
the old ones to be all destroyed. In living bodies, variation will
cause the slight alterations, generation will multiply them almost
infinitely, and natural selection will pick out with unerring skill
each improvement. Let this process go on for millions of years; and
during each year on millions of individuals of many kinds; and may
we not believe that a living optical instrument might thus be formed
as superior to one of glass, as the works of the Creator are to
those of man?
Modes of Transition
If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed, which
could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight
modifications, my theory would absolutely break down. But I can find
out no such case. No doubt many organs exist of which we do not know
the transitional grades, more especially if we look to much-isolated
species, round which, according to the theory, there has been much
extinction. Or again, if we take an organ common to all the members of
a class, for in this latter case the organ must have been originally
formed at a remote period, since which all the many members of the
class have been developed; and in order to discover the early
transitional grades through which the organ has passed, we should have
to look to very ancient ancestral forms, long since become extinct.
We should be extremely cautious in concluding that an organ could
not have been formed by transitional gradations of some kind. Numerous
cases could be given amongst the lower animals of the same organ
performing at the same time wholly distinct functions; thus in the
larva of the dragon-fly and in the fish Cobitis the alimentary canal
respires, digests, and excretes. In the Hydra, the animal may be
turned inside out, and the exterior surface will then digest and the
stomach respire. In such cases natural selection might specialise,
if any advantage were thus gained, the whole or part of an organ,
which had previously performed two functions, for one function
alone, and thus by insensible steps greatly change its nature. Many
plants are known which regularly produce at the same time
differently constructed flowers; and if such plants were to produce
one kind alone, a great change would be effected with comparative
suddenness in the character of the species. It is, however, probable
that the two sorts of flowers borne by the same plant were
originally differentiated by finely graduated steps, which may still
be followed in some few cases.
Again, two distinct organs, or the same organ under two very
different forms, may simultaneously perform in the same individual the
same function, and this is an extremely important means of transition:
to give one instance,- there are fish with gills or branchiae that
breathe the air dissolved in the water, at the same time that they
breathe free air in their swimbladders, this latter organ being
divided by highly vascular partitions and having a ductus
pneumaticus for the supply of air. To give another instance from the
vegetable kingdom: plants climb by three distinct means, by spirally
twining, by clasping a support with their sensitive tendrils, and by
the emission of aerial rootlets; these three means are usually found
in distinct groups, but some few species exhibit two of the means,
or even all three, combined in the same individual. In all such
cases one of the two organs might readily be modified and perfected so
as to perform all the work, being aided during the progress of
modification by the other organ; and then this other organ might be
modified for some other and quite distinct purpose, or be wholly
obliterated.
The illustration of the swimbladder in fishes is a good one, because
it shows us clearly the highly important fact that an organ originally
constructed for one purpose, namely, flotation, may be converted
into one for a widely different purpose, namely, respiration. The
swimbladder has, also, been worked in as an accessory to the
auditory organs of certain fishes. All physiologists admit that the
swimbladder is homologous, or "ideally similar" in position and
structure with the lungs of the higher vertebrate animals: hence there
is no reason to doubt that the swimbladder has actually been converted
into lungs, or an organ used exclusively for respiration.
According to this view it may be inferred that all vertebrate
animals with true lungs are descended by ordinary generation from an
ancient and unknown prototype, which was furnished with a floating
apparatus or swimbladder. We can thus, as I infer from Owen's
interesting description of these parts, understand the strange fact
that every particle of food and drink & which we swallow has to pass
over the orifice of the trachea, with some risk of falling into the
lungs, notwithstanding the beautiful contrivance by which the
glottis is closed. In the higher Vertebrate the branchiae have
wholly disappeared- but in the embryo the slits on the sides of the
neck and the loop-like course of the arteries still mark their
former position. But it is conceivable that the now utterly lost
branchiae might have been gradually worked in by natural selection for
some distinct purpose: for instance, Landois has shown that the
wings of insects are developed from the tracheae; it is therefore
highly probable that in this great class organs which once served
for respiration have been actually converted into organs for flight.
In considering transitions of organs, it is so important to bear
in mind the probability of conversion from one function to another,
that I will give another instance. Pedunculated cirripedes have two
minute folds of skin, called by me the ovigerous frena, which serve,
through the means of a sticky secretion, to retain the eggs until they
are hatched within the sack. These cirripedes have no branchiae, the
whole surface of the body and of the sack, together with the small
frena, serving for respiration. The Balanidae or sessile cirripedes,
on the other hand, have no ovigerous frena, the eggs lying loose at
the bottom of the sack, within the well-enclosed shell; but they have,
in the same relative position with the frena, large, much-folded
membranes, which freely communicate with the circulatory lacunae of
the sack and body, and which have been considered by all naturalists
to act as branchiae. Now I think no one will dispute that the
ovigerous frena in the one family are strictly homologous with the
branchiae of the other family; indeed, they graduate into each
other. Therefore it need not be doubted that the two little folds of
skin, which originally served as ovigerous frena, but which, likewise,
very slightly aided in the act of respiration, have been gradually
converted by natural selection into branchiae simply through an
increase in their size and the obliteration of their adhesive
glands. If all pedunculated cirripedes had become extinct, and they
have suffered far more extinction than have sessile cirripedes, who
would ever have imagined that the branchiae in this latter family
had originally existed as organs for preventing the ova from being
washed out of the sack?
There is another possible mode of transition, namely, through the
acceleration or retardation of the period of reproduction. This has
lately been insisted on by Prof. Cope and others in the United States.
It is now known that some animals are capable of reproduction at a
very early age, before they have acquired their perfect characters;
and if this power became thoroughly well developed in a species, it
seems probable that the adult stage of development would sooner or
later be lost; and in this case, especially if the larva differed much
from the mature form, the character of the species would be greatly
changed and degraded. Again, not a few animals, after arriving at
maturity, go on changing in character during nearly their whole lives.
With mammals, for instance, the form of the skull is often much
altered with age, of which Dr. Murie has given some striking instances
with seals; every one knows how the horns of stags become more and
more branched, and the plumes of some birds become more finely
developed, as they grow older. Prof. Cope states that the teeth of
certain lizards change much in shape with advancing years; with
crustaceans not only many trivial, but some important parts assume a
new character, as recorded by Fritz Muller, after maturity. In all
such cases,- and many could be given,- if the age for reproduction
were retarded, the character of the species, at least in its adult
state, would be modified; nor is it improbable that the previous and
earlier stages of development would in some cases be hurried through
and finally lost. Whether species have often or ever been modified
through this comparatively sudden mode of transition, I can form no
opinion; but if this has occurred, it is probable that the differences
between the young and the mature, and between the mature and the
old, were primordially acquired by graduated steps.
Special Difficulties of the Theory Of Natural Selection
Although we must be extremely cautious in concluding that any
organ could not have been produced by successive, small,
transitional gradations, yet undoubtedly serious cases of difficulty
occur.
One of the most serious is that of neuter insects, which are often
differently constructed from either the males or fertile females;
but this case will be treated of in the next chapter. The electric
organs of fishes offer another case of special difficulty; for it is
impossible to conceive by, what steps these wondrous organs have
been produced. But this is not surprising, for we do not even know
of what use they are. In the Gymnotus and torpedo they no doubt
serve as powerful means of defence, and perhaps for securing prey; yet
in the ray, as observed by Matteucci, an analogous organ in the tail
manifests but little electricity, even when the animal is greatly
irritated; so little, that it can hardly be of any use for the above
purposes. Moreover, in the ray, besides the organ just referred to,
there is, as Dr. R. McDonnell has shown, another organ near the
head, not known to be electrical, but which appears to be the real
homologue of the electric battery in the torpedo. It is generally
admitted that there exists between these organs and ordinary muscle
a close analogy, in intimate structure, in the distribution of the
nerves, and in the manner in which they are acted on by various
reagents. It should, also, be especially observed that muscular
contraction is accompanied by an electrical discharge; and, as Dr.
Radcliffe insists, "in the electrical apparatus of the torpedo
during rest, there would seem be a charge in every respect like that
which is met with in muscle and nerve during rest, and the discharge
of the torpedo, instead of being peculiar, may be only another form of
the discharge which depends upon the action of muscle and motor
nerve." Beyond this we cannot at present go in the way of explanation;
but as we know so little about the uses of these organs, and as we
know nothing about the habits and structure of the progenitors of
the existing electric fishes, it would be extremely bold to maintain
that no serviceable transitions are possible by which these organs
might have been gradually developed.
These organs appear at first to offer another and far more serious
difficulty; for they occur in about a dozen kinds of fish, of which
several are widely remote in their affinities. When the same organ
is found in several members of the same class, especially if in
members having very different habits of life, we may generally
attribute its presence to inheritance from a common ancestor; and
its absence in some of the members to loss through disuse or natural
selection. So that, if the electric organs had been inherited from
some one ancient progenitor, we might have expected that all
electric fishes would have been specially related to each other; but
this is far from the case. Nor does geology at all lead to the
belief that most fishes formerly possessed electric organs, which
their modified descendants have now lost. But when we look at the
subject more closely, we find in the several fishes provided with
electric organs, that these are situated in different parts of the
body,- that they differ in construction, as in the arrangement of
the plates, and, according to Pacini, in the process or means by which
the electricity is excited- and lastly, in being supplied with
nerves proceeding from different sources, and this is perhaps the most
important of all the differences. Hence in the several fishes
furnished with electric organs, these cannot be considered as
homologous, but only as analogous in function. Consequently there is
no reason to suppose that they have been inherited from a common
progenitor; for had this been the case they would have closely
resembled each other in all respects. Thus the difficulty of an organ,
apparently the same, arising in several remotely allied species,
disappears, leaving only the lesser yet still great difficulty;
namely, by what graduated steps these organs have been developed in
each separate group of fishes.
The luminous organs which occur in a few insects, belonging to
widely different families, and which are situated in different parts
of the body, offer, under our present state of ignorance, a difficulty
almost exactly parallel with that of the electric organs. Other
similar cases could be given; for instance in plants, the very curious
contrivance of a mass of pollen-grains, borne on a foot-stalk with
an adhesive gland, is apparently the same in Orchis and Asclepias,-
genera almost as remote as is possible amongst flowering plants; but
here again the parts are not homologous. In all cases of beings, far
removed from each other in the scale of organisation, which are
furnished with similar and peculiar organs, it will be found that
although the general appearance and function of the organs may be
the same, yet fundamental differences between them can always be
detected. For instance, the eyes of cephalopods or cuttle-fish and
of vertebrate animals appear wonderfully alike; and in such widely
sundered groups no part of this resemblance can be due to
inheritance from a common progenitor. Mr. Mivart has advanced this
case as one of special difficulty, but I am unable to see the force of
his argument. An organ for vision must be formed of transparent
tissue, and must include some sort of lens for throwing an image at
the back of a darkened chamber. Beyond this superficial resemblance,
there is hardly any real similarity between the eyes of cuttle-fish
and vertebrates, as may be seen by consulting Hensen's admirable
memoir on these organs in the Cephalopoda. It is impossible for me
here to enter on details, but I may specify a few of the points of
difference. The crystalline lens in the higher cuttle-fish consists of
two parts, placed one behind the other like two lenses, both having
a very different structure and disposition to what occurs in the
vertebrata. The retina is wholly different, with an actual inversion
of the elemental parts, and with a large nervous ganglion included
within the membranes of the eye. The relations of the muscles are as
different as it is possible to conceive, and so in other points. Hence
it is not a little difficult to decide how far even the same terms
ought to be employed in describing the eyes of the Cephalopoda and
Vertebrata. It is, of course, open to any one to deny that the eye
in either case could have been developed through the natural selection
of successive slight variations; but if this be admitted in the one
case, it is clearly possible in the other; and fundamental differences
of structure in the visual organs of two groups might have been
anticipated, in accordance with this view of their manner of
formation. As two men have sometimes independently hit on the same
invention, so in the several foregoing cases it appears that natural
selection, working for the good of each being, and taking advantage of
all favourable variations, has produced similar organs, as far as
function is concerned, in distinct organic beings, which owe none of
their structure in common to inheritance from a common progenitor.
Fritz Muller, in order to test the conclusions arrived at in this
volume, has followed out with much care a nearly similar line of
argument. Several families of crustaceans include a few species,
possessing an air-breathing apparatus and fitted to live out of the
water. In two of these families, which were more especially examined
by Muller and which are nearly related to each other, the species
agree most closely in all important characters; namely, in their sense
organs, circulating system, in the position of the tufts of hair
within their complex stomachs, and lastly in the whole structure of
the water-breathing branchiae, even to the microscopical hooks by
which they are cleansed. Hence it might have been expected that in the
few species belonging to both families which live on the land, the
equally important air-breathing apparatus would have been the same;
for why should this one apparatus, given for the same purpose, have
been made to differ, whilst all the other important organs were
closely similar or rather identical?
Fritz Muller argues that this close similarity in so many points
of structure must, in accordance with the views advanced by me, be
accounted for by inheritance from a common progenitor. But as the vast
majority of the species in the above two families, as well as most
other crustaceans, are aquatic in their habits, it is improbable in
the highest degree, that their common progenitor should have been
adapted for breathing air was thus led carefully to examine the
apparatus in the air-breathing species; and he found it to differ in
each in several important points, as in the position of the
orifices, in the manner in which they are opened and closed, and in
some accessory details. Now such differences are intelligible, and
might even have been expected, on the supposition that species
belonging to distinct families had slowly become adapted to live
more and more out of water, and to breathe the air. For these species,
from belonging to distinct families, would have differed to a
certain extent, and in accordance with the principle that the nature
of each variation depends on two factors, viz., the nature of the
organism and that of the surrounding conditions, their variability
assuredly would not have been exactly the same. Consequently natural
selection would have had different materials or variations to work on,
in order to arrive at the same functional result; and the structures
thus acquired would almost necessarily have differed. On the
hypothesis of separate acts of creation the whole case remains
unintelligible. This line of argument seems to have had great weight
in leading Fritz Muller to accept the views maintained by me in this
volume.
Another distinguished zoologist, the late Professor Claparide, has
argued in the same manner, and has arrived at the same result. He
shows that there are parasitic mites (Acaridae), belonging to distinct
sub-families and families, which are furnished with hair-claspers.
These organs must have been independently developed, as they could not
have been inherited from a common progenitor; and in the several
groups they are formed by the modification of the fore-legs,- of the
hind-legs,- of the maxillae or lips,- and of appendages on the under
side of the hind part of the body.
In the foregoing cases, we see the same end gained and the same
function performed, in beings not at all or only remotely allied, by
organs in appearance, though not in development, closely similar. On
the other hand, it is a common rule throughout nature that the same
end should be gained, even sometimes in the case of closely-related
beings, by the most diversified means. How differently constructed
is the feathered wing of a bird and the membrane-covered wing of a
bat; and still more so the four wings of a butterfly, the two wings of
a fly, and the two wings with the elytra of a beetle. Bivalve shells
are made to open and shut, but on what a number of patterns is the
hinge constructed,- from the long row of neatly interlocking teeth
in a Nucula to the simple ligament of a Mussel! Seeds are disseminated
by their minuteness,- by their capsule being converted into a light
balloon-like envelope,- by being embedded in pulp or flesh, formed
of the most diverse parts, and rendered nutritious, as well as
conspicuously coloured, so as to attract and be devoured by birds,- by
having hooks and grapnels of many kinds and serrated arms, so as to
adhere to the fur of quadrupeds,- and by being furnished with wings
and plumes, as different in shape as they are elegant in structure, so
as to be wafted by every breeze. I will give one other instance; for
this subject of the same end being gained by the most diversified
means well deserves attention. Some authors maintain that organic
beings have been formed in many ways for the sake of mere variety,
almost like toys in a shop, but such a view of nature is incredible.
With plants having separated sexes, and with those in which, though
hermaphrodites, the pollen does not spontaneously fall on the
stigma, some aid is necessary for their fertilisation. With several
kinds this is effected by the pollen-grains, which are light and
incoherent, being blown by the wind through mere chance on to the
stigma; and this is the simplest plan which can well be conceived.
An almost equally simple, though very different, plan occurs in many
plants in which a symmetrical flower secretes a few drops of nectar,
and is consequently visited by insects; and these carry the pollen
from the anthers to the stigma.
From this simple stage we may pass through an inexhaustible number
of contrivances, all for the same purpose and effected in
essentially the same manner, but entailing changes in every part of
the flower. The nectar may be stored in variously shaped
receptacles, with the stamens and pistils modified in many ways,
sometimes forming trap-like contrivances, and sometimes capable of
neatly adapted movements through irritability or elasticity. From such
structures we may advance till we come to such a case of extraordinary
adaptation as that lately described by Dr. Cruger in the Coryanthes.
This orchid has part of its labellum or lower lip hollowed out into
a great bucket, into which drops of almost pure water continually fall
from two secreting horns which stand above it; and when the bucket
is half full, the water overflows by a spout on one side. The basal
part of the labellum stands over the bucket, and is itself hollowed
out into a sort of chamber with two lateral entrances; within this
chamber there are curious fleshy ridges. The most ingenious man, if he
had not witnessed what takes place, could never have imagined what
purpose all these parts serve. But Dr. Cruger saw crowds of large
humble-bees visiting the gigantic flowers of this orchid, not in order
to suck nectar, but to gnaw off the ridges within the chamber above
the bucket; in doing this they frequently pushed each other into the
bucket, and their wings being thus wetted they could not fly away, but
were compelled to crawl out through the passage formed by the spout or
overflow. Dr. Cruger saw a "continual procession" of bees thus
crawling out of their involuntary bath. The passage is narrow, and
is roofed over by the column, so that a bee, in forcing its way out,
first rubs its back against the viscid stigma and then against the
viscid glands of the pollen-masses. The pollen-masses are thus glued
to the back of the be which first happens to crawl out through the
passage of a lately expanded flower, and are thus carried away. Dr.
Cruger sent me a flower in spirits of wine, with a bee which he had
killed before it had quite crawled out with a pollen-mass still
fastened to its back. When the bee, thus provided, flies to another
flower, or to the same flower a second time, and is pushed by its
comrades into the bucket and then crawls out by the passage, the
pollen-mass necessarily comes first into contact with the viscid
stigma, and adheres to it, and the flower is fertilised. Now at last
we see the full use of every part of the flower, of the
water-secreting horns, of the bucket half full of water, which
prevents the bees from flying away, and forces them to crawl out
through the spout, and rub against the properly placed viscid
pollen-masses and the viscid stigma.
The construction of the flower in another closely allied orchid,
namely the Catasetum, is widely different, though serving the same
end; and is equally curious. Bees visit these flowers, like those of
the Coryanthes, in order to gnaw the labellum; in doing this they
inevitably touch a long, tapering, sensitive projection, or, as I have
called it, the antenna. This antenna, when touched, transmits a
sensation or vibration to a certain membrane which is instantly
ruptured; this sets free a spring by which the pollen-mass is shot
forth, like an arrow, in the right direction, and adheres by its
viscid extremity to the back of the bee. The pollen-mass of the male
plant (for the sexes are separate in this orchid) is thus carried to
the flower of the female plant where it is brought into contact with
the stigma, which is viscid enough to break certain elastic threads,
and retaining the pollen, fertilisation is effected.
How, it may be asked, in the foregoing and in innumerable other
instances, can we understand the graduated scale of complexity and the
multifarious means for gaining the same end. The answer no doubt is,
as already remarked, that when two forms vary, which already differ
from each other in some slight degree, the variability will not be
of the same exact nature, and consequently the results obtained
through natural selection for the same general purpose will not be the
same. We should also bear in mind that every highly developed organism
has passed through many changes; and that each modified structure
tends to be inherited, so that each modification will not readily be
quite lost, but may be again and again further altered. Hence the
structure of each part of each species, for whatever purpose it may
serve, is the sum of many inherited changes, through which the species
has passed during its successive adaptations to changed habits and
conditions of life.
Finally then, although in many cases it is most difficult even to
conjecture by what transitions organs have arrived at their present
state; yet, considering how small the proportion of living and known
forms is to the extinct and unknown, I have been astonished how rarely
an organ can be named, towards which no transitional grade is known to
lead. It certainly is true, that new organs appearing as if created
for some special purpose, rarely or never appear in any being;- as
indeed is shown by that old, but somewhat exaggerated, canon in
natural history of "Natura non facit saltum." We meet with this
admission in the writings of almost every experienced naturalist; or
as Milne Edwards has well expressed it, Nature is prodigal in variety,
but niggard in innovation. Why, on the theory of Creation, should
there be so much variety and so little real novelty? Why should all
the parts and organs of many independent beings, each supposed to have
been separately created for its proper place in nature, be so commonly
linked together by graduated steps? Why should not Nature take a
sudden leap from structure to structure? On the theory of natural
selection, we can clearly understand why she should not; for natural
selection acts only by taking advantage of slight successive
variations; she can never take a great and sudden leap, but must
advance by short and sure, though slow steps.
Organs of little apparent Importance, as affected by Natural
Selection
As natural selection acts by life and death,- by the survival of the
fittest, and by the destruction of the less well-fitted
individuals,- I have sometimes felt great difficulty in
understanding the origin or formation of parts of little importance;
almost as great, though of a very different kind, as in the case of
the most perfect and complex organs.
In the first place, we are much too ignorant in regard to the
whole economy of any one organic being, to say what slight
modifications would be of importance or not. In a former chapter I
have given instances of very trifling characters, such as the down
on fruit and the colour of its flesh, the colour of the skin and
hair of quadrupeds, which, from being correlated with constitutional
differences or from determining the attacks of insects, might
assuredly be acted on by natural selection. The tail of the giraffe
looks like an artificially constructed fly-flapper; and it seems at
first incredible that this could have been adapted for its present
purpose by successive slight modifications, each better and better
fitted, for so trifling an object as to drive away flies; yet we
should pause before being too positive even in this case, for we
know that the distribution and existence of cattle and other animals
in South America absolutely depend on their power of resisting the
attacks of insects: so that individuals which could by any means
defend themselves from these small enemies, would be able to range
into new pastures and thus gain a great advantage. It is not that
the larger quadrupeds are actually destroyed (except in some rare
cases) by flies, but they are incessantly harassed and their
strength reduced, so that they are more subject to disease, or not
so well enabled in a coming dearth to search for food, or to escape
from beasts of prey.
Organs now of trifling importance have probably in some cases been
of high importance to an early progenitor, and, after having been
slowly perfected at a former period, have been transmitted to existing
species in nearly the same state, although now of very slight use; but
any actually injurious deviations in their structure would of course
have been checked by natural selection. Seeing how important an
organ of locomotion the tail is in most aquatic animals, its general
presence and use for many purposes in so many land animals, which in
their lungs or modified swimbladders betray their aquatic origin,
may perhaps be thus accounted for. A well-developed tail having been
formed in an aquatic animal, it might subsequently come to be worked
in for all sorts of purposes,- as a fly-flapper, an organ of
prehension, or as an aid in turning, as in the case of the dog, though
the aid in this latter respect must be slight, for the hare, with
hardly any tail, can double still more quickly.
In the second place, we may easily err in attributing importance
to characters, and in believing that they have been developed
through natural selection. We must by no means overlook the effects of
the definite action of changed conditions of life,- of so-called
spontaneous variations, which seem to depend in a quite subordinate
degree on the nature of the conditions,- of the tendency to
reversion to long-lost characters,- of the complex laws of growth,
such as of correlation, compensation, of the pressure of one part on
another, &c.,- and finally of sexual selection, by which characters of
use to one sex are often gained and then transmitted more or less
perfectly to the other sex, though of no use to this sex. But
structures thus indirectly gained, although at first of no advantage
to a species, may subsequently have been taken advantage of by its
modified descendants, under new conditions of life and newly
acquired habits.
If green woodpeckers alone had existed, and we did not know that
there were many black and pied kinds, I dare say that we should have
thought that the green colour was a beautiful adaptation to conceal
this tree-frequenting bird from its enemies; and consequently that
it was a character of importance, and had been acquired through
natural selection; as it is, the colour is probably in chief part
due to sexual selection. A trailing palm in the Malay Archipelago
climbs the loftiest trees by the aid of exquisitely constructed
hooks clustered around the ends of the branches, and this contrivance,
no doubt, is of the highest service to the plant; but as we see nearly
similar hooks on many trees which are not climbers, and which, as
there is reason to believe from the distribution of the
thorn-bearing species in Africa and South America, serve as a
defence against browsing quadrupeds, so the spikes on the palm may
at first have been developed for this object, and subsequently have
been improved and taken advantage of by the plant, as it underwent
further modification and became a climber. The naked skin on the
head of a vulture is generally considered as a direct adaptation for
wallowing in putridity; and so it may be, or it may possibly be due to
the direct action of putrid matter; but we should be very cautious
in drawing any such inference, when we see that the skin on the head
of the clean-feeding male turkey is likewise naked. The sutures in the
skull? of young mammals have been advanced as a beautiful adaptation
for aiding parturition, and no doubt they facilitate, or may be
indispensable for this act; but as sutures occur in the skulls of
young birds and reptiles, which have only to escape from a broken egg,
we may infer that this structure has arisen from the laws of growth,
and has been taken advantage of in the parturition of the higher
animals.
We are profoundly ignorant of the cause of each slight variation
or individual difference; and we are immediately made conscious of
this by reflecting on the differences between the breeds of our
domesticated animals in different countries,- more especially in the
less civilised countries where there has been but little methodical
selection. Animals kept by savages in different countries often have
to struggle for their own subsistence, and are exposed to a certain
extent to natural selection, and individuals with slightly different
constitutions would succeed best under different climates. With cattle
susceptibility to the attacks of flies is correlated with colour, as
is the liability to be poisoned by certain plants; so that even colour
would be thus subjected to the action of natural selection. Some
observers are convinced that a damp climate affects the growth of
the hair, and that with the hair the horns are correlated. Mountain
breeds always differ from lowland breeds; and a mountainous country
would probably affect the hind limbs from exercising them more, and
possibly even the form of the pelvis; and then by the law of
homologous variation, the front limbs and the head would probably be
affected. The shape, also, of the pelvis might affect by pressure
the shape of certain parts of the young in the womb. The laborious
breathing necessary in high regions tends, as we have good reason to
believe, to increase the size of the chest; and again correlation
would come into play. The effects of lessened exercise together with
abundant food on the whole organisation is probably still more
important; and this, as H. von Nathusius has lately shown in his
excellent treatise, is apparently one chief cause of the great
modification which the breeds of swine have undergone. But we are
far too ignorant to speculate on the relative importance of the
several known and unknown causes of variation; and I have made these
remarks only to show that, if we are unable to account for the
characteristic differences of our several domestic breeds, which
nevertheless are generally admitted to have arisen through ordinary
generation from one or a few parent-stocks, we ought not to lay too
much stress on our ignorance of the precise cause of the slight
analogous differences between true species.
Utilitarian Doctrine, how far true: Beauty, how acquired.
The foregoing remarks lead me to say a few words on the protest
lately made by some naturalists, against the utilitarian doctrine that
every detail of structure has been produced for the good of its
possessor. They believe that many structures have been created for the
sake of beauty, to delight man or the Creator (but this latter point
is beyond the scope of scientific discussion), or for the sake of mere
variety, a view already discussed. Such doctrines, if true, would be
absolutely fatal to my theory. I fully admit that many structures
are now of no direct use to their possessors, and may never have
been of any use to their progenitors; but this does not prove that
they were formed solely for beauty or variety. No doubt the definite
action of changed conditions, and the various causes of modifications,
lately specified, have all produced an effect, probably a great
effect, independently of any advantage thus gained. But a still more
important consideration is that the chief part of the organisation
of every living creature is due to inheritance; and consequently,
though each being assuredly is well fitted for its place in nature,
many structures have now no very close and direct relation to
present habits of life. Thus, we can hardly believe that the webbed
feet of the upland goose or of the frigate-bird are of special use
to these birds; we cannot believe that the similar bones in the arm of
the monkey, in the fore-leg of the horse, in the wing of the bat,
and in the flipper of the seal, are of special use to these animals.
We may safely attribute these structures to inheritance. But webbed
feet no doubt were as useful to the progenitor of the upland goose and
of the frigate-bird, as they now are to the most aquatic of living
birds. So we may believe that the progenitor of the seal did not
possess a flipper, but a foot with five toes fitted for walking or
grasping; but we may further venture to believe that the several bones
in the limbs of the monkey, horse, and bat, were originally developed,
on the principle of utility, probably through the reduction of more
numerous bones in the fin of some ancient fish-like progenitor of
the whole class. It is scarcely possible to decide how much
allowance ought to be made for such causes of change, as the
definite action of external conditions, so-called spontaneous
variations, and the complex laws of growth; but with these important
exceptions, we may conclude that the structure of every living
creature either now is, or was formerly, of some direct or indirect
use to its possessor.
With respect to the belief that organic beings have been created
beautiful for the delight of man,- a belief which it has been
pronounced is subversive of my whole theory,- I may first remark
that the sense of beauty obviously depends on the nature of the
mind, irrespective of any real quality in the admired object; and that
the idea of what is beautiful, is not innate or unalterable. We see
this, for instance, in the men of different races admiring an entirely
different standard of beauty in their women. If beautiful objects
had been created solely for man's gratification, it ought to be
shown that before man appeared, there was less beauty on the face of
the earth than since he came on the stage. Were the beautiful volute
and cone shells of the Eocene epoch, and the gracefully sculptured
ammonites of the Secondary period, created that man might ages
afterwards admire them in his cabinet? Few objects are more
beautiful than the minute siliceous cases of the diatomaceae: were
these created that they might be examined and admired under the higher
powers of the microscope? The beauty in this latter case, and in
many others, is apparently wholly due to symmetry of growth. Flowers
rank amongst the most beautiful productions of nature; but they have
been rendered conspicuous in contrast with the green leaves, and in
consequence at the same time beautiful, so that they may be easily
observed by insects. I have come to this conclusion from finding it an
invariable rule that when a flower is fertilised by the wind it
never has a gaily-coloured corolla. Several plants habitually
produce two kinds of flowers; one kind open and coloured so as to
attract insects; the other closed, not coloured, destitute of
nectar, and never visited by insects. Hence we may conclude that, if
insects had not been developed on the face of the earth, our plants
would not have been decked with beautiful flowers, but would have
produced only such poor flowers as we see on our fir, oak, nut and ash
trees, on grasses, spinach, docks, and nettles, which are all
fertilised through the agency of the wind. A similar line of
argument holds good with fruits; that a ripe strawberry or cherry is
as pleasing to the eye as to the palate,- that the gaily-coloured
fruit of the spindle-wood tree and the scarlet berries of the holly
are beautiful objects,- will be admitted by every one. But this beauty
serves merely as a guide to birds and beasts, in order that the
fruit may be devoured and the matured seeds disseminated: I infer that
this is the case from having as yet found no exception to the rule
that seeds are always thus disseminated when embedded within a fruit
of any kind (that is within a fleshy or pulpy envelope), if it be
coloured of any brilliant tint, or rendered conspicuous by being white
or black.
On the other hand, I willingly admit that a great number of male
animals, as all our most gorgeous birds, some fishes, reptiles, and
mammals, and a host of magnificently coloured butterflies, have been
rendered beautiful for beauty's sake; but this has been effected
through sexual selection, that is, by the more beautiful males
having been continually preferred by the females, and not for the
delight of man. So it is with the music of birds. We may infer from
all this that a nearly similar taste for beautiful colours and for
musical sounds runs through a large part of the animal kingdom. When
the female is as beautifully coloured as the male, which is not rarely
the case with birds and butterflies, the cause apparently lies in
the colours acquired through sexual selection having been
transmitted to both sexes, instead of to the males alone. How the
sense of beauty in its simplest form- that is, the reception of a
peculiar kind of pleasure from certain colours, forms, and sounds- was
first developed in the mind of man and of the lower animals, is a very
obscure subject. The same sort of difficulty is presented, if we
enquire how it is that certain flavours and odours give pleasure,
and others displeasure. Habit in all these cases appears to have
come to a certain extent into play; but there must be some fundamental
cause in the constitution of the nervous system in each species.
Natural selection cannot possibly produce any modification in a
species exclusively for the good of another species; though throughout
nature one species incessantly takes advantage of, and profits by, the
structures of others. But natural selection can and does often produce
structures for the direct injury of other animals, as we see in the
fang of the adder, and in the ovipositor of the ichneumon, by which
its eggs are deposited in the living bodies of other insects. If it
could be proved that any part of the structure of any one species
had been formed for the exclusive good of another species, it would
annihilate my theory, for such could not have been produced through
natural selection. Although many statements may be found in works on
natural history to this effect, I cannot find even one which seems
to me of any weight. It is admitted that the rattlesnake has a
poison-fang for its own defence, and for the destruction of its
prey; but some authors suppose that at the same time it is furnished
with a rattle for its own injury, namely, to warn its prey. I would
almost as soon believe that the cat curls the end of its tail when
preparing to spring, in order to warn the doomed mouse. It is a much
more probable view that the rattlesnake uses its rattle, the cobra
expands its frill, and the puff-adder swells whilst hissing so
loudly and harshly, in order to alarm the many birds and beasts
which are known to attack even the most venomous species. Snakes act
on the same principle which makes the hen ruffle her feathers and
expand her wings when a dog approaches her chickens; but I have not
space here to enlarge on the many ways by which animals endeavour to
frighten away their enemies.
Natural selection will never produce in a being any structure more
injurious than beneficial to that being, for natural selection acts
solely by and for the good of each. No organ will be formed, as
Paley has remarked, for the purpose of causing pain or for doing an
injury to its possessor. If a fair balance be struck between the
good and evil caused by each part, each will be found on the whole
advantageous. After the lapse of time, under changing conditions of
life, if any part comes to be injurious, it will be modified; or if it
be not so, the being Will become extinct as myriads have become
extinct.
Natural selection tends only to make each organic being as perfect
as, or slightly more perfect than, the other inhabitants of the same
country with which it comes into competition. And we see that this
is the standard of perfection attained under nature. The endemic
productions of New Zealand, for instance, are perfect one compared
with another; but they are now rapidly yielding before the advancing
legions of plants and animals introduced from Europe. Natural
selection will not produce absolute perfection, nor do we always meet,
as far as we can judge, with this high standard under nature. The
correction for the aberration of light is said by Muller not to be
perfect even in that most perfect organ, the human eye. Helmholtz,
whose judgment no one will dispute, after describing in the
strongest terms the wonderful powers of the human eye, adds these
remarkable words: "That which we have discovered in the way of
inexactness and imperfection in the optical machine and in the image
on the retina, is as nothing in comparison with the incongruities
which we have just come across in the domain of the sensations. One
might say that nature has taken delight in accumulating contradictions
in order to remove all foundation from the theory of a pre-existing
harmony between the external and internal worlds." If our reason leads
us to admire with enthusiasm a multitude of inimitable contrivances in
nature, this same reason tells us, though we may easily err on both
sides, that some other contrivances are less perfect. Can we
consider the sting of the bee as perfect, which, when used against
many kinds of enemies, cannot be withdrawn, owing to the backward
serratures, and thus inevitably causes the death of the insect by
tearing out its viscera?
If we look at the sting of the bee, as having existed in a remote
progenitor, as a boring and serrated instrument, like that in so
many members of the same great order, and which has since been
modified but not perfected for its present purpose, with the poison
originally adapted for some other object, such as to produce galls,
since intensified, we can perhaps understand how it is that the use of
the sting should so often cause the insect's own death: for if on
the whole the power of stinging be useful to the social community,
it will fulfil all the requirements of natural selection, though it
may cause the death of some few members. If we admire the truly
wonderful power of scent by which the males of many insects find their
females, can we admire the production for this single purpose of
thousands of drones, which are utterly useless to the community for
any other purpose, and which are ultimately slaughtered by their
industrious and sterile sisters? It may be difficult, but we ought
to admire the savage instinctive hatred of the queen-bee, which
urges her to destroy the young queens, her daughters, as soon as
they are born, or to perish herself in the combat; for undoubtedly
this is for the good of the community; and maternal love or maternal
hatred, though the latter fortunately is most rare, is all the same to
the inexorable principle of natural selection. If we admire the
several ingenious contrivances, by which orchids and many other plants
are fertilised through insect agency, can we consider as equally
perfect the elaboration of dense clouds of pollen by our fir trees, so
that a few granules may be wafted by chance on to the ovules?
Summary: the Law of Unity of Type and of the Conditions of Existence
embraced by the Theory of Natural Selection
We have in this chapter discussed some of the difficulties and
objections which may be urged against the theory. Many of them are
serious; but I think that in the discussion light has been thrown on
several facts, which on the belief of independent acts of creation are
utterly obscure. We have seen that species at any one period are not
indefinitely variable, and are not linked together by a multitude of
intermediate gradations, partly because the process of natural
selection is always very slow, and at any one time acts only on a
few forms; and partly because the very process of natural selection
implies the continual supplanting and extinction of preceding and
intermediate gradations. Closely allied species, now living on a
continuous area, must often have been formed when the area was not
continuous, and when the conditions of life did not insensibly
graduate away from one part to another. When two varieties are
formed in two districts of a continuous area, an intermediate
variety will often be formed, fitted for an intermediate zone; but
from reasons assigned, the intermediate variety will usually exist
in lesser numbers than the two forms which it connects; consequently
the two latter, during the course of further modification, from
existing in greater numbers, will have a great advantage over the less
numerous intermediate variety, and will thus generally succeed in
supplanting and exterminating it.
We have seen in this chapter how cautious we should be in concluding
that the most different habits of life could not graduate into each
other; that a bat, for instance, could not have been formed by natural
selection from an animal which at first only glided through the air.
We have seen that a species under new conditions of life may
change its habits; or it may have diversified habits, with some very
unlike those of its nearest congeners. Hence we can understand,
bearing in mind that each organic being is trying to live wherever
it can live, how it has arisen that there are upland geese with webbed
feet, ground woodpeckers, diving thrushes, and petrels with the habits
of auks.
Although the belief that an organ so perfect as the eye could have
been formed by natural selection, is enough to stagger any one; yet in
the case of any organ, if we know of a long series of gradations in
complexity, each good for its possessor, then, under changing
conditions of life, there is no logical impossibility in the
acquirement of any conceivable degree of perfection through natural
selection. In the cases in which we know of no intermediate or
transitional states, we should be extremely cautious in concluding
that none can have existed, for the metamorphoses of many organs
show what wonderful changes in function are at least possible. For
instance, a swimbladder has apparently been converted into an
air-breathing lung. The same organ having performed simultaneously
very different functions, and then having been in part or in whole
specialised for one function; and two distinct organs having performed
at the same time the same function, the one having been perfected
whilst aided by the other, must often have largely facilitated
transitions.
We have seen that in two beings widely remote from each other in the
natural scale, organs serving for the same purpose and in external
appearance closely similar may have been separately and
independently formed; but when such organs are closely examined,
essential differences in their structure can almost always be
detected; and this naturally follows from the principle of natural
selection. On the other hand, the common rule throughout nature is
infinite diversity of structure for gaining the same end; and this
again naturally follows from the same great principle.
In many cases we are far too ignorant to be enabled to assert that a
part or organ is so unimportant for the welfare of a species, that
modifications in its structure could not have been slowly
accumulated by means of natural selection. In many other cases,
modifications are probably the direct result of the laws of
variation or of growth, independently of any good having been thus
gained. But even such structures have often, as we may feel assured,
been subsequently taken advantage of, and still further modified,
for the good of species under new conditions of life. We may, also,
believe that a part formerly of high importance has frequently been
retained (as the tail of an aquatic animal by its terrestrial
descendants), though it has become of such small importance that it
could not, in its present state, have been acquired by means of
natural selection.
Natural selection can produce nothing in one species for the
exclusive good or injury of another; though it may well produce parts,
organs, and excretions highly useful or even indispensable, or again
highly injurious to another species, but in all cases at the same time
useful to the possessor. In each well-stocked country natural
selection acts through the competition of the inhabitants, and
consequently leads to success in the battle for life, only in
accordance with the standard of that particular country. Hence the
inhabitants of one country, generally the smaller one, often yield
to the inhabitants of another and generally the larger country. For in
the larger country there will have existed more individuals and more
diversified forms, and the competition will have been severer, and
thus the standard of perfection will have been rendered higher.
Natural selection will not necessarily lead to absolute perfection;
nor, as far as we can judge by our limited faculties, can absolute
perfection be everywhere predicated.
On the theory of natural selection we can clearly understand the
full meaning of that old canon in natural history, "Natura non facit
saltum." This canon, if we look to the present inhabitants alone of
the world, is not strictly correct; but if we include all those of
past times, whether known or unknown, it must on this theory be
strictly true.
It is generally acknowledged that all organic beings have been
formed on two great laws: Unity of Type, and the Conditions of
Existence. By unity of type is meant that fundamental agreement in
structure which we see in organic beings of the same class, and
which is quite independent of their habits of life. On my theory,
unity of type is explained by unity of descent. The expression of
conditions of existence, so often insisted on by the illustrious
Cuvier, is fully embraced by the principle of natural selection. For
natural selection acts by either now adapting the varying parts of
each being to its organic and inorganic conditions of life; or by
having adapted them during past periods of time: the adaptations being
aided in many cases by the increased use or disuse of parts, being
affected by the direct action of the external conditions of life,
and subjected in all cases to the several laws of growth and
variation. Hence, in fact, the law of the Conditions of Existence is
the higher law; as it includes, through the inheritance of former
variations and adaptations, that of Unity of Type.
To flip through the pages of my BOS faster...
|