Cnidaria (jellyfish, sea anemones, corals and their relatives)

Back to Chapter 2 Back to Case studies Previous case study - simple animals Next case study - worms
*** SUMMARY of Conclusions reached References


The box jellyfish Chironex fleckeri. Courtesy of www.barrierreefaustralia.com.

The subkingdom Eumetazoa (so-called "true" animals) is made up of 33 phyla; most have tissues organized into organs and organ systems (World Biodiversity Database, 2000). The simplest of these phyla are the cnidaria (commonly known as coelenterates, including animals such as jellyfish, sea anemones, corals and freshwater hydra). Cnidaria have a body wall that is made up of only two layers of cells, like that of sponges; other "true" animals (eumetazoa) have three. Unlike sponges, cnidaria possess a basic kind of body symmetry: they are radially symmetrical.

Cnidaria have a rudimentary nervous system, described by Abramson:

Neurons are located regularly over the surface of the animal, and, like a net, they are in contact with those nearest to it. The effect of such an arrangement is that a stimulus applied to any part of the animal will be directed to all parts, much like sticking your finger in a cup of jello will make the whole mass move... The propagation of a nerve impulse is not transmitted along a linear chain of neurons, but radiates from its point of origin. Such a system is not conducive to fine control of motor movements (1994, p. 176, italics mine).

Fine-tuning behaviour may suggest the capacity for control over one's actions, and hence agency. So far, we have found that all cellular organisms, including bacteria and plants, are capable of directed movement. However, bacteria have only two ways of moving - "run" (keep moving in the same direction) and "tumble" (random). Plants are capable of moving in the direction of sunlight, water or gravity, but this movement can hardly be called "fine-tuned" as the parts of a plant do not work in a co-ordinated fashion to adjust the motion of the organism. (I shall discuss fine-tuning in more detail in the sections on worms and insects.)

R.7 All cellular organisms are capable of directed movement.

R.8 Only organisms with central nervous systems are capable of fine-tuning their bodily movements.

Although cnidaria do not possess a central nervous system, let alone a brain, their nerve net permits rapid communication between cells (in some cases taking only milliseconds), over relatively long distances. In "simpler" animals, which lack neurons, communication can only occur between neighbouring cells. Prescott (2001) considers the behaviour of cnidaria to be an important advance over that of sponges, which respond only to direct stimulation, at a very slow rate (about twenty minutes). By contrast, cnidaria exhibit "internally generated, rhythmic behavior, and co-ordinated patterns of motor response to complex sensory stimuli", allowing them to display an "integrated global response" to their environment (Prescott, 2001, pp. 5, 7). In some cnidaria, such as the hydrozoan jellyfish, the nerve net is arranged in a longitudinal circuit which supports fast attack, escape and defense reactions (Prescott, 2001, pp. 6-7). The cnidarian nervous system is described more fully in an Appendix.

Nervous systems and brains are unique to animals; they are not found in any other kingdom of organisms (World Biodiversity Database, 2000). The philosophical issues here are whether the possession of a nervous system confers any new abilities on its bearer that are relevant to the possession of a mind, and whether having a nervous system is a necessary and/or sufficient condition for cognition.

Vision in cnidaria?

Cubozoans, or killer box jellyfish, are known to have complex eyes, similar in their basic design to those of vertebrates, despite the absence of a brain or central nervous system. The eyes connect into the neural network of the jellyfish, and there is evidence that they can see images. It has been suggested that for cubozoans, vision may play a role in feeding and reproductive behaviour:

Certain cubozoans are know to chase small fish and seize them with their tentacles. Further, many cubozoans exhibit complex sexual behaviors in which the males chase the females, grasp them with a tentacle, and subsequently inject packets of sperm into them. Vision may be important to the jellyfish for such complex behaviors (Martin, 2000).

Assuming that Martin's proposals prove to be correct, should we regard cubozoans as having mental states relating to events in their environment? For instance, are they aware of the world around them? I would argue that before we can impute mental states to these jellyfish, it needs to be shown that they are capable of internally generated flexible behaviour (Conclusion N.12). If they follow fixed action patterns when pursuing prey and mating, then the ascription of mental states is redundant. The relevant questions are: how do cnidaria act, and can they learn?

Agency in cnidaria?

Prescott considers the nervous system found in cnidaria to be a fundamental advance in the evolution of what he calls "action selection" or the problem of "resolving conflicts between competing behavioural alternatives" (2001, p. 1).

Action slection is an essential epistemic condition for the identification of mental states: an observer could never identify an organism as having a mind unless it possessed a repertoire of actions, combined with the ability to select the most appropriate one for the present circumstances.

N.14 An organism must have an action selection mechanism before it can be said to have cognitive mental states.

Unfortunately, this requirement does not take us very far. All organisms possess some ability to adjust to rapidly fluctuating environmental conditions: bacteria can adapt to changes in their food type and plants can respond in a sophisticated manner to changes in local lighting conditions (Godfrey-Smith, 2001, pp. 6-7). Prescott himself (2001, p. 1) acknowledges that action selection is part of a wider problem faced by all living creatures: behavioural integration, or the task of co-ordinating the activities of their parts and sub-systems. Nevertheless, he contends that the speed and co-ordination of the cnidarian response to stimuli represents a different kind of behaviour from that displayed by "simpler" animals such as sponges.

In some jellyfish, the nerve net is functionally divided into two relatively independent systems - one for feeding and the other for movement - which interact in neuron clusters. Others possess a single nerve net which can carry two different types of action potentials enabling either rapid escape swimming (to avoid predators), or, slow rhythmic swimming for feeding (Prescott, 2001, pp. 5-7).

Prescott likens this decentralised neural arrangement to the subsumption architecture described by Brooks (1986), which could be summed up in the adage, "You've got to crawl before you can walk". Rather than trying to build human intelligence into robots, Brooks designed a computer architecture that would display the range of functionality found in so-called "simple" life forms such as insects. Brooks argued that insects are "almost characterizable as deterministic machines". His architecture describes how an "agent" (be it a robot or a simple animal) can behave reliably in an unpredictable environment, despite having nothing more than cheap, small information processors, simple sensors and low memory. A Brooksian "agent" has no central control: it is hierarchically organised from the bottom up. Control is distributed between different components, making the "agent" better able to withstand damage (i.e. more robust). Behaviour patterns are hard-wired, and sensors and actuators (which produce movement) are closely coupled, to allow rapid response times. Co-ordination between the different components is ensured by built-in timers and by having behaviour modules that can inhibit one another. Simple behaviours combine to produce more complex patterns of behaviour (Laird, 1994). According to Prescott, the functional subdivision of the nerve net into two distinct circuits for feeding and movement, which is found in some jellyfish and sea anemones, resembles the Brooksian architecture proposed for some behaviour-based robots (2001, p. 6).

Can we regard an organism instantiating Brooks' architecture as having mental states? One could argue that some kind of primitive intelligence is required to co-ordinate the response of a motile, multicellular organism to a complex, unpredictable environment. This is the line of argument endorsed by Godfrey-Smith (2001), who has formulated his Environmental Complexity Thesis (ECT) to explain the evolution of cognition:

The function of cognition is to enable the agent to deal with environmental complexity.

The term "function" here is meant to be understood in a strong sense: the function of a trait is what it was selected for, in the course of its evolution. Godfrey-Smith defines "cognition" broadly, to include any kind of behaviour involving the coordination of actions with perceived environmental conditions. Naturally, he does not regard cognition as an on-off trait but as a trait that is found to some degree in all organisms - even those which are incapable of learning. However, we have argued that a mind-neutral intentional stance provides an adequate account of the adaptive behaviour found in bacteria, protoctista, plants and "simple" animals. The term "cognitive" is a superfluous here.

In any case, the specifications of Brooks' architecture make the ascription of mental states to a Brooksian "agent" redundant. A Brooksian "agent" has a very "low-tech" design. It has no internal model of the outside world - according to Brooks' design philosophy, such a system lacks the "computing" resources required to model a world which is dynamic and unpredictable. Additionally, a Brooksian "agent" does not engage in planning or learning of any kind. All of its behaviour is hard-wired and built-in, to ensure co-ordination and cope with unforeseen contingencies. In other words, its action patterns are fixed. If cnidaria do indeed behave like Brooksian "agents", then they cannot learn new ways of responding to unforeseen events. For reasons discussed above (Conclusion N.11), the ascription of cognitive mental states to cnidaria would then be redundant, as it would tell us nothing useful about their behaviour. A mind-neutral, goal-centred intentional stance would suffice.

Can cnidaria learn?

Habituation has been documented in cnidaria (Encyclopedia Britannica, 1989). As we saw above, habituation does not qualify as "true" learning, according to the criteria given by Kilian and Muller (2001, pp. 2-4), who argue that flexibility of response patterns is a requirement for "true" learning. Kilian and Muller propose that "true" learning is possible "only when several cells of information transfer functionality come into close contact spatially, i.e. in organisms with central nervous systems" (2001, p. 4, italics mine). Do cnidaria exhibit "true" learning?

I have not been able to locate any reports of experiments testing whether cnidaria are capable of associative learning. Clearly more work needs to be done in this area. For instance, one could repeatedly pair an unconditioned stimulus which causes a rapid escape response in hydrozoan jellyfish with the presence of light (a conditioned stimulus), and attempt to induce a conditioned rapid escape response to the presence of light alone.

Certainly, the cnidaria possess biologically significant features that other creatures lacking minds do not - in particular, a nervous system which (in some cases) allows very fast signal conduction as well as (possibly) reflexes, and enables fast attack, escape, or defense reactions. It would be a mistake to equate the behavioural repertoire of cnidaria with that of bacteria or even plants. Unlike bacteria, cnidaria are multicellular creatures, which face the task of co-ordinating their entire bodies in response to sudden changes in their environment. For instance, swimming in jellyfish requires the "synchronous, simultaneous contraction of the entire perimeter of the bell" (Prescott, 2001, p. 7). And while plants, like cnidaria, are multicellular, plants are not motile. There is no plant analogue of a rapid escape response.

It may turn out to be the case that some cnidaria are capable of internally generated flexible behaviour, and have minds after all. However, the evidence to date suggests that the sensory capacities and behaviour modification observed in cnidaria can be adequately described using a mind-neutral intentional stance. There is no evidence that they possess an internal mechanism enabling them to modify their behaviour patterns and learn to do something new or different, so there is no warrant at present for ascribing mental states to them.

S.11 The fact that an organism has an action selection mechanism, sensors and a nervous system with reflexes, does not provide a sufficient warrant for the ascription of mental states to it.

So far, my search for cognitive mental states in viruses, bacteria, protoctista, plants, animal cells, simple animals or animals with nerve nets has not yielded any positive results. On the other hand, because there is a slim possibility that all eukaryotes, at least, are capable of associative learning, we cannot definitively rule out mental states for these creatures, either.

Back to Chapter 2 Back to Case studies Previous case study - simple animals Next case study - worms
*** SUMMARY of Conclusions reached References